CAPITAL (DAS KAPITAL) (Vol. 3)
by
Karl Marx
(Foreign Languages Publishing House translation)
Part V: Profits
FUTURECASTS online magazine
www.futurecasts.com
Vol. 6, No. 4, 4/1/04.
Karl Marx: |
Volume 1, Part II: "Contradictions in Capitalist Industrialization." |
|
Introduction to Vol. 3, Parts V & VI
Making value disappear:
& |
Marx finally confronts his
fundamental irresolvable problem in Volume 3. There are numerous processes
and incentives in the capitalist system that obviously contribute greatly to its
productivity yet don't involve industrial labor. For his propaganda purposes,
Marx must disparage them and maintain his view that they are of no
"value." & |
It is impossible to rationally discuss common economic phenomena with "profits" as redefined by Marx.
Both Marx and Engels continuously trip up when applying "profits" as Marx redefines that term to phenomena that can only be explained by "profits" as normally defined. |
Of course, he fails. He throws up numerous
examples of capitalist abuses and confusing clouds of obscuring detail about the
business cycle. This provides much grist for Marx's propaganda mill and an
emotional smokescreen with which the weaknesses of Das Kapital are hidden. |
Differences in the
productivity of individual capitalists also begin to gain recognition in
Volume 3. (Capitalist facilities are not homogeneous masses, all of which
might collapse together as overproduction and overcapacity squeeze profits.) Yet,
he still expects a general collapse. He mentions such differences only in
passing while discussing other things. |
|
Engels considered Volume 3 the most
important of the volumes of Das Kapital. In this, he is undoubtedly correct,
although there is considerable doubt as to whether all these assorted
notes always included Marx' final considered opinions. In this volume, Marx - supplemented by Engels - finally deals at length with
profits in its varying forms as industrial and mercantile profits, as interest
and as rent. In Volume 3, Marx finally attacks the problem of "profits"
directly and aggressively. With some semantics slight-of-hand, he radically
redefines the terms "profits" and "total capital," and then
pretends that they describe the same phenomena as when normally defined.
(Needless to say, such an effort inevitably becomes an exercise of extraordinary stupidity.) & Nevertheless, Volume 3 is the least read - perhaps because it is a daunting 890 pages in length - not counting Engels' usual 20 page Preface. Volume 4, produced well after Engels' death, is primarily an account of the history of the theory of surplus value and - mercifully - of so little import as to be readily disregarded. & Volume 3 has more of Engels in it than any other volume, although he assures us that his arrangements, supplementations and additions were all carefully in line with the notes and thoughts of Karl Marx. In particular, Marx failed to fulfill his long-standing promise to provide an explanation of financial capital that reconciled its obvious roles in capitalist productivity with the contention by Marx that it added no value to capitalist production. & For example, Part 2 of Chapter 6 of Volume 3 begins with the acknowledgement that world markets and the credit system are essential to an understanding of the capitalist system, and provides assurance that they will be covered in the "continuation" of Volume 3 after "the general nature of capital" is explained. He does, in fact, herein provide voluminous material on the monetary and financing mechanisms of capitalism and their uses. & |
|
The financial system bestows many "benefits" on the productive and distributional systems, but no "value." |
Yet again, a distinction without a
difference is the ultimate propaganda ploy resorted to. The financial system
bestows many "benefits" on the productive and distributional systems,
but no "value." See, Karl Marx, Capital (Das
Kapital) vol. 3 (II), "Interest, Rent, and Labor Use-Values," at
"I) Interest and Returns on Equity Capital." He fails to explain how
these financial mechanisms can be so useful - indeed, admittedly essential - and yet not contribute to the
"value" created by the system. He hides this failure behind his usual
emotional smokescreen by instead passionately emphasizing the abuses and
periodic failures of the system. & The coverage of rents is the most logical part of Das Kapital. It is also the subject with which Marx is most in agreement with Adam Smith. Unlike Smith, however, Marx - as is expected - emphasizes the problems and costs of private ownership of land while disparaging the benefits - indeed, the essentiality - of private property. |
H) Profits
The influence of labor use-values on profits:
& |
There had already arisen a "Marxist
School" of socialist economists churning out interpretative material by the time of publication of Volume 3
of Das Kapital in 1894. They
were wandering in various directions, struggling to make sense of the concepts
presented in the first two volumes, and to preserve them in the face of a
reality that observably - perversely - refused to conform to Marx's "scientifically" determined economic "laws."
Thus, in the beginning, in Friedrich Engels'
Preface and in the body of Volume 3, Engels and Marx spend some time and ink trying
by means of criticism and explanation to channel this diverse flow of
rationalization into the course they believed appropriate. & |
How can profits be dictated by total capital when only the use-value of industrial labor power provides the surplus value from which it is derived? |
The
important problem of profits is addressed by Engels in his usual 20 page
preface.. As Engels had pointed out in Volume 2 - and
everyone starting with Adam Smith recognized - profits depend not just on
industrial capital and labor, but on the total capital employed during a given
time. "Accordingly, equal sums of capital yield equal profits in equal time
spans," regardless of the particular mix of industrial productive and overhead
capital, circulating capital, and/or financial capital. How can profits be dictated by total capital when only the use-value of industrial labor power provides the surplus value from which it is derived?
To answer this, Engels abandons the concentration in the first
two volumes on the workings of individual businesses and industries. In
general agreement with one Peter Fireman, Engels relies instead on averages for the economy as a whole.
"Fireman has indeed placed his finger on the salient point," Engels
says. Variances from the averages, according to Fireman, are just
"predictable disturbances" in the workings of the economic
"laws" of Marx and in no way refute them. |
Goods can thus be circulated in the market at prices substantially above their "value" - above the costs defined by Marx as "socially necessary" - and that variance can be maintained indefinitely. Other goods can be marketed at prices below their "value" - for indefinite periods - without driving producers out of business - without causing capital to flee from that industry. |
Marx, too, in volume 3, has taken this route. Marx's
theory of value in fact does not apply to businesses and industries, but somehow
manifests itself only in average profit rates for an economy as a whole. Some
industries run above average, and some below, but "the total sum of prices
remains equal to the total sum of values." Moreover - horror of horrors -
these averages are admittedly based on commercial capital as well as industrial
capital. See, "The rate of profit," below.
Nevertheless, as Marx elsewhere acknowledges, fluctuations between
products are not "mutually cancelled." Some products remain inherently
above "value" levels, and some below. (This is obviously a very
weak "law of Nature," indeed.)
All forms of capital - including commercial forms - now suddenly play a role in determining profits and market prices and even values based on "socially necessary" activities, since the averaging out in the marketplace acknowledged by Marx and Engels is done on the basis of commercial as well as industrial capital - overhead as well as factory capital. Thus, profits are transformed into portions of surplus value that are distributed according to the total capital of specific entities regardless of the surplus value each entity produced.
|
Marx radically redefines the terms "profits" and "total capital," and then pretends that they describe the same phenomena as when normally defined. |
This is clearly inconsistent with the view of Marx,
asserted as early as Volume 1, that, although lurking behind the scenes, his
"values" regulate fluctuations in the market. Yet, Marx, too, in
Volume 3 retreats to the assertion that it is only at the national level that
"the mass of profit is identical with the mass of the surplus-value, and
with the surplus value itself." Marx ultimately retreats even from this
proposition. Towards the end of Volume 3, Marx excludes "ground-rents"
on raw land from "profits" but not from surplus value. |
Cost price:
& |
Another concept, "cost-price," is introduced
at the beginning of Volume 3. Marx introduces this new segmentation and engages
in this new round of twisted rationalization to refute some Marxist School
economists - specifically Robert Torrens, George Ramsay and Pierre J. Proudhon -
who had enmeshed themselves in Marx-like efforts to account for the source of profits from
the "values" incorporated in commodities. & |
"Cost-price" includes just the capital "advanced" by the capitalist as "constant" and "variable" capital. |
Marx distinguishes the "cost" of commodities - the "cost-price" - measured by the expended industrial capital, from the larger "actual cost" - measured by the expenditure - the labor use-values - of industrial labor - which includes surplus-value. Cost-price is thus a much narrower concept than the "cost of goods sold," which is used in actual business management and accounting practice. "Cost-price" includes just the capital "advanced" by the capitalist as "constant" and "variable" capital.
|
Once again, Marx feels impelled to assert the practical economic
importance of this additional segmentation that he here elaborates. He
emphasizes that "cost-price" is not just a bookkeeping convention. It
constitutes an essential part of capitalist production, since it covers the
maintenance of productive capital.
|
|
To the capitalist, these distinctions are
invisible, Marx must here again admit - as with all his other special distinctions. The
capitalist sees only his "cost-price" and the value of the commodities
produced. The distinction between Marx's variable capital and constant capital is
invisible. The capitalist sees only the distinction between fixed and circulating
capital.
|
The capitalist sees only that his total capital has produced an increase - a profit, as that term is normally defined. He does not see that only his expenditures for industrial wages have produced the increase.
Marx cites Malthus: "The capitalist - - - expects an equal
profit upon all the parts of the capital which he advances." Yet again,
Marx confounds "surplus-value" with "profit" as normally
defined. He produces
his mathematical formula again with p substituted for s as if the two were
synonymous. They may be for Marx - but not for Malthus.
|
|
Sales below "cost-price" will cause a reduction of productive capital. Thus, "the capitalist is inclined to regard cost-price as the true inner value of the commodities, because it is the price required for the bare conservation of his capital." This is the price required to prevent the disappearance of his "advanced capital."
|
The rate of profit:
& |
Marx now appropriates established economic terms
and phrases - "profits" and "total capital" - and
redefines them - leaving bourgeois economists with not even a language with
which to express their views. It is not enough for him to just introduce his new
terms and phrases as necessary to accurately explain his concepts. |
Like surplus value, profits are limited only by expenses for industrial wages and industrial assets and materials - which are already "pregnant" with surplus value. |
|
But, why then is this concept of "profits" needed, if it is so analogous to "surplus value?"
|
|
"Total capital" includes capital advanced for merchant activities. |
Merchant's capital also earns on average the equalized rate of profit. When he gets to his segment dealing with commercial factors, he perforce inconsistently has to expand his view of "total capital" so that it can be applied in the context of merchants and other commercial factors. This automatically expands "total capital" to take in the industrialist's purchasing and marketing offices.
|
|
In surplus value, the relation between capital and the exploitation of labor "is laid bare." |
But if profit and surplus value averages are quantitatively so similar, why has Marx gone to so much trouble in defining and explaining surplus value? Because profits appear to come from total capital, while in surplus value, the relation between capital and the exploitation of labor "is laid bare."
Marx then summarizes again his recognition that the realization of these rates for individual capitalists or industries are dependent on the vicissitudes of the market. Commodities can be sold at above or below their values. This merely alters the division of surplus value, not its quantity or rate. The processes of circulation and marketing complicate the picture but merely determine how values are divided. These complications permit the erroneous bourgeois view that surplus values can be derived from all capital expenditures - even independently without any industrial labor - rather than just industrial wages. However, he cannot abandon his view, elaborated in Volume 1, that the "values" he has defined act as a hidden force regulating all these price movements over time.
Marx and Engels then provide 27 pages of pseudo scientific mathematical reasoning covering a wide variety of permutations of these "rates of profits" and "rates of surplus value." At best, the economics described by these calculations is grossly simplistic. However, since these "rates" are totally immaterial, the mathematics are equally immaterial. As they perforce frequently admit, all of these calculations are invisible to capitalists and thus are of no consideration in how capitalists conduct their business.
|
Competition forces producers to pass the lions share of all cost decreases on to their customers. |
Then, Marx analyzes how the "rate of profit" increases with improvements in various aspects of production - with "economy of constant capital" - such as a shortening of the rate of turnover or the recycling of scrap materials or an increase in the scale of production or productivity of machinery - the quantity and rate of "surplus value" remaining equal. He follows this with changes in industrial material and equipment valuations. He assumes herein that "commodities are sold at their values, so that price fluctuations caused by competition do not as yet concern us."
The tendency of profit rates to decline over
time with improvements in capitalist production have been evident since the
time of Adam Smith, and Marx extensively analyzes it. Indeed, Marx at
several points notes the competitive squeeze experienced by industrialists
when some particular productive advance is under rapid development,
rendering existing equipment prematurely less valuable. Competition forces
producers to pass the lions share of all cost decreases on to their
customers. |
Irrationally drawing a broad conclusion from his narrow, monopoly example, Marx asserts that it is this ability to increase profits by reductions in the costs of raw materials that drives capitalists to favor cost reductions and elimination of tariffs. He criticizes Ricardo for discussing the advantages of world trade on the basis of "general principles" without recognition of its influence "on the rate of profit."
|
|
Competition overwhelms all efforts at stabilization. |
With competition, surplus value itself is affected when costs are reduced due to more efficient use of materials and equipment. That is why employers so fanatically insist on the most efficient and least costly methods of production. Indeed, competition is so powerful that it constantly forces the capitalist to cut costs and improve the efficiency of production - to the point of cheating on quality and failing to provide safe working conditions.
Marx then, again, provides detail from the abundant examples of horribles available in 19th century industrial history - here, 15 pages in addition to that already provided in previous volumes of Das Kapital. He attributes these conditions solely to the capitalist mode of production.
In similar mode, Marx continues for about 25 pages explaining
simplistically how various price and productivity fluctuations impact the rates of profits and surplus value. He repeatedly runs these through
his
mathematical models. He concludes that capitalist industrial development, by
constantly increasing the demand for raw materials - especially those of an
agricultural nature - must constantly increase the volatility of price
fluctuations as periods of surplus follow periods of scarcity and back again in
response to rapidly fluctuating prices.
Clearly, it is only by the provision of more goods to consumers at
these lower costs - by the provision of more benefits for consumers - that
profits can increase as a result of cost decreases. For Marx, this is expressed as the squeezing of more surplus labor out of workers by working
them harder or putting more of them to work to serve the new and increased
markets. In this way, capitalism increases the
“amount” of profits, which, unlike the “rate of profits,” is
“identical” to the “amount” of surplus value. Providing employment is
inherently exploitative. |
Immaterial:
& |
But profits tend to equalize for capital regardless
of industry and other characteristics. Although further elaborating how whole
industries can vary in their rates of profit and surplus value, Marx ultimately
must deal with this observation. Risk factors, which are considered elsewhere by Marx, impact this
phenomenon to the extent they cannot be insured against. & |
He asserts again that goods are only on average sold at their
"value" in the market. Some goods are sold above value and some
below. Thus, some capitalists realize less than their fair share of surplus
value from the market, and others more - and this tends to equalize profits
regardless on the types of capital used and the extent of surplus value
extracted from labor. & |
"Under capitalist production, the general law [of industrial labor use-value] acts as the prevailing tendency only in a very complicated and approximate manner, as a never ascertainable average of ceaseless fluctuations." |
Marx's phenomena apply only to capitalists as a class.
|
The "rate of profit," as Marx defines it, varies.
However, here, too, there is a "general rate of profit" for
the economy as a whole that changes only slowly, Marx notes, because more rapid particular
changes tend to balance each other out.
|
The realities of surplus value hidden under the surface are for the first time revealed by Marx in Das Kapital..
Marx provides about 60 pages discussing the various permutations of
these disconnects between prices and values, averaged profits and varying rates
of profits. (But, it is all "immaterial.") He continues to confound
"profit" as he defines it with profit as normally defined - citing
again Malthus that "every part of a capital yields a uniform profit."
He provides a discussion of profits averaged "under pressure of
competition" on the basis of the "masses of capital" employed in
each sphere of production - again confounding his narrow definition of
capital - industrial assets plus wages - for a phenomenon that is based on the
much broader normal definition of capital.
|
|
Marx thus tries to apply standard economic market theory to
his specialized concepts and redefinitions of existing concepts. For those who
do not understand the semantics games he is playing, it all sounds as reasonable
as does standard economic theory.
|
Prices and price movements are "dominated" by "the law of value," Marx asserts. Value "is the center of gravity" around which prices tend to fluctuate. "[The] law of value regulates the prices of production."
|
|
Market price is not in fact determined by supply and demand, Marx asserts, but independently of them, because factors outside the market - factors of industrial production - observably move market prices. If the factors increase or decrease permanently, the change in market prices is correspondingly permanent.
Indeed, beginning in the very next paragraph, Marx extensively
explains that competition and "the fluctuations of market-prices which
correspond to the fluctuations of demand and supply, tend continuously" to
equate prices with values. Further, here again, Marx notes that those in the
market are concerned only with market prices. Buyers and sellers know nothing of
"values" as defined by Marx. He recognizes a wide array of factors at play in the demand
side of the equation. |
Yet, again, Marx confounds his concepts of "profit" and "rate of profit" with the normal meanings of those terms, in explaining once again why capital flows satisfy the natural demand of capital to receive the "average profit." |
Capital in developed nations knows not distance, and knows no distinction between the various "spheres of production." The development and flexibility of the markets for capital, labor and goods determine the speed of market adjustments. Yet, again, Marx confounds his concepts of "profit" and "rate of profit" with the normal meanings of those terms, in explaining once again why capital flows satisfy the natural demand of capital to receive the "average profit."
Capitalists thus have a common interest in increasing their ability to exploit labor - and will act together to further that interest. The "intensity of exploitation of the sum total of labour by the sum total of capital" determines the "average profit" enjoyed by all capital.
|
Profit rates tend to decline as capitalist systems develop.
This was explained by Adam Smith a century before Marx, and Marx's explanation -
attributing the phenomenon solely to the relative expansion of capital invested
in industrial facilities and materials - is at least a logical part of the full
correct explanation. For once, his definitions of "rates of profit"
and "total capital" logically provide a conclusion similar to that
using the normal definitions.
Marx discusses a number of influences that can counteract this
tendency. However, they just slow it down rather than ending it. An increased
intensity of labor exploitation by such means as lengthening the working day or
speeding up the machinery or being a first mover with new improvements in
machinery or productive procedures, a temporary depression of wages below
subsistence levels, declining costs of productive assets, persistent and growing
rates of unemployment, the development of new industries - primarily producing
"luxury" goods, certain aspects of foreign trade, are among the
factors he analyzes in his usual style. |
Internal contradictions that undermine capital:
& |
There are
inherent contradictions in the capitalist system that continuously undermine
its stability and must ultimately destroy it. These contradictions are made
manifest during periodic crises, which serve violently to wrench matters back
into balance, only to launch capital at an ever accelerating rate back on its
course towards ultimate collapse. & |
Constant increases in production also outrun markets due to the subsistence levels at which wages are kept.
Capitalism is a system driven to constant increases in production for the limited purpose of further expansion of production. Production is "an end in itself."
"A rift must continually ensue between the limited dimensions of consumption under capitalism and a production which forever tends to exceed this immanent barrier." |
Capitalist incentives constantly drive both capitalist
expansion and increases in productivity. Constant increases in production create
competitive pressures that drive down prices and profit rates and force even more efforts at
increased productivity. But technical advances accelerate the depreciation of
existing capital. Constant increases in production also outrun markets due to
the subsistence levels at which wages are kept.
|
Many small holders accumulate capital that they are unable to employ as profit rates decline and the sums of capital needed for suitably profitable employment increase. Credit intermediaries develop to put unneeded capital at interest or other return into the hands of those who can use it. "The mass of small dispersed capitals is thereby driven along the adventurous road of speculation, credit frauds, stock swindles, and crises."& |
|
Capitalist expansion stimulates rapid population growth,
which inevitably proceeds faster than the increased labor can all be
productively employed. Expansion of production balances against the constant
squeeze on profits that drives capitalists to maximize productivity so that more
work can be performed by fewer workers. During periodic crises, the result is
readily observable in the ever increasing armies of the unemployed. During periodic crises, competition between capitalists as holders of capital
breaks
out. & |
The need for consumable products does not end just because the means of payment is lacking.
Not enough means of production are produced to permit the employment of the entire able-bodied population under the most productive conditions so that their absolute working period could be shortened by the mass and effectiveness of the constant capital employed during working-hours."
"[Capitalism] comes to a standstill at a point fixed by the production and realisation of profit, and not the satisfaction of requirements." |
Marx interprets the process of crisis in accordance with his own concepts. Prices and wages are driven sharply lower, productivity is ruthlessly increased by all available means, capital values of all kind drop sharply, and the army of unemployed grows. Ultimately, the weakest capitalists are driven under, increased productivity permits profitable operation by the survivors on the basis of capital of diminished value, permitting recovery of profit rates and resumption of profitable operation for the survivors.
"Over-production" is an excess of capital, not an excess of means of production or commodities when viewed from outside the capitalist system. The need for consumable products does not end just because the means of payment is lacking.
Problems with the over-production of consumable commodities are apparent in the business cycle, Marx points out. He criticizes those economists who deny that such over-production exists. However, such over-production exists only in the sense that there is insufficient means to pay, not because there is a lack of need.
|
The flow of capital into foreign markets seeking the higher profits available there eases somewhat this surfeit of capital. The capital outflow does not cause a capital shortage at home, but exists alongside the continued expansion of domestic capital. However, it spreads capitalist production methods and problems to new markets, worldwide. Thus, this tendency for profit rates to decline has rightly been of great concern for bourgeois economists like Ricardo. For when the rate of profit gets too low, new capitalist offshoots and small capitalists can't make up the difference in volume. All capitalist activity concentrates in a few large hands. The ability of capitalism to progress - to continue its expansion - ends.
|
|
|
Merchants:
& |
At last, Marx focuses on commercial factors. He begins by examining the differences when commodities are brought to
market by merchants rather than by employees of industrialists. After all the
nasty things he has previously said about them, Marx now inconsistently discovers that merchants do in fact provide some important advantages that even
he must recognize. & |
Merchant expertise facilitates marketing and increases the efficiency of commerce. They can both diversify and gain the benefits of scale by merchandising many different products and/or similar products from several producers. |
By facilitating commerce, the
activities of merchants in normal times help bring prices down for consumers
while maintaining profit levels for capital. In other words, they increase the
productivity of capital generally. |
"But no value is produced in the process of circulation, and, therefore, no surplus-value."
|
Nevertheless, the merchant adds no value to the commodities sold, Marx must still insist. The industrialist allows himself to be exploited by the merchant in order to gain all the benefits of the merchant’s activities – benefits that the industrial laborers do not participate in. To support this contention, he still has nothing to offer but his basic tautological reasoning. Ignoring the benefits, he relies instead on his narrow definitions to assert that the merchant has produced no “surplus value”.
|
Commerce "realizes, but does not create, values." Marx still relies on nothing more than distinctions without a difference. The merchant can only realize the values already existing in the commodities. "Merchant's capital therefore does not create either value or surplus-value, at least not directly." However, by the benefits bestowed, it can increase the scale and productivity of industrial capital, the value created by industrial capital, and the profitability of industrial capital.
|
Merchant's reap profits from this process not independently
by their activities, but by sharing in the industrialist's profits. The
industrialist sells his commodities to the merchant at a price below its
"value" in order to more conveniently circulate his capital in his
productive process. This permits the merchant - by selling at
"value" - to gain the merchant's profit.
In this, the merchant's wage-workers are like the back office workers
of the industrialist. They don't create value - they just help to "realize" it -
and as such they share by their wages in the industrialist's profit. If the
industrialist did not deal through merchants, his own staff would have to do the
work of the merchant's staff. |
|
By financing its capital needs, merchants can buy before they accumulate the necessary capital. This borrowed money is exchanged with industrial capitalists when purchasing their products. This lends elasticity to production and circulation that can become overstretched. It permits both merchants and producers to continue operations beyond what can be timely sold to consumers, resulting in disruptions - crises - that "violently" restore equilibrium.
|
The underlying regulatory power of industrial labor power is hidden from view even more for commercial factors than for industrialists. Prices do, indeed, vary widely and frequently fail to reflect such "values." It is only in the averages for society as a whole that such values determine competitive prices.
|
Marx then examines how commercial activities give the appearance of
affecting and determining prices independently of the factors of production. The
underlying regulatory power of industrial labor power is hidden from view even
more for commercial factors than for industrialists. Prices do, indeed, vary
widely and frequently fail to reflect such "values." It is only in the
averages for society as a whole that such values determine competitive prices.
|
Banks and other factors in the financing mechanism also operate,
as do merchants, as specialists that increase the efficiency of capital by the
efficient conduct of the necessary functions of money. They finance operations,
safeguard "hoards" that act as reserves or await investment
opportunity, make payments and accept receipts, square accounts, exchange
different forms of money, and so forth, as needed to facilitate the flow of
money-capital through the productive and commercial cycles of capital
circulation. This activity "concentrates, shortens, and simplifies"
the technical operations of money circulation. It substantially increases the
turnover rate of money-capital, thus increasing efficiency and reducing the sums needed for operations. |
Up to this point, credit-capital has been lurking in the background,
as Marx sometimes notes the ability to borrow capital. Here, Marx finally deals
with credit operations - the money lending of "money-dealers." This
segment here occupies just half a page. See,
Karl Marx, Capital (Das
Kapital) vol. 3 (II), "Interest, Rent, and Use-Values," at
"I) Interest and Returns on Equity Capital."
|
|
There is no value in the transportation and
distribution of goods for consumption across substantial distances to places where they are
otherwise not available. Marx maintains this untenable position even when
discussing trade between nations in centuries past when the difficulties and
dangers of travel were great. Before the rise of capitalist production,
commercial profit "not only appears as outbargaining and cheating, but also
largely originates from them."
|
The abstract industrial labor theory of value defended:
& |
Skeptics
were not satisfied with the arguments advanced in Volume 3, and so Engels
felt impelled to add a 17 page supplement to later editions in defense of Marx's
concept.
|
See, Marx, "Capital (Das Kapital)" Volume 1, Part I: "Abstract Labor Standard of Value," and Volume 1, Part II: "Contradictions in Capitalist Industrialization," and Volume 2, Part III: "The Circulation & Expansion of Capital," and Volume 2, Part IV: "Criticism of Adam Smith," and Volume 3, Part VI: "Interest, Rent & Labor Use-Values." |
Please return to our Homepage and e-mail your name and comments.
Copyright © 2004 Dan Blatt