FUTURECASTS BOOK Trade War "Understanding the Great Depression Explaining the Great Depression, its Trade War, and failures of "New" Keynesian interest rate suppression policy without ideological clap trap, theory confirmation bias or political spin. |
CONTENTS
PUBLISHER'S INTRODUCTION THE WEALTH OF NATIONS by ADAM SMITH |
1 5
|
Introduction: Market Mechanisms and
Administered Alternatives |
5 |
Part I: Markets (Book I) |
8 |
Part II: Capital (Book II)
|
40 |
Part III: Property Rights (Book III) |
56 |
Part IV: Mercantilism (Book IV) |
59 |
Part V: The Proper Role of Government (Book V)
|
87
|
PRINCIPLES by DAVID RICARDO Introduction:
Comments on Smith, Malthus, Say and Others |
113 113 |
Part I: Value |
117 |
Part II: Rent Prices, Wages and Profits |
128 |
Part III: International Trade and Comparative Advantage |
138 |
Part IV: Say's Law and Inadequate Demand |
150 |
Part V: Taxes and War Debts
|
154
|
CAPITAL (DAS KAPITAL) by KARL MARX Book
I: Value Determined by an Abstract Labor Standard |
163 163 |
Introduction to Book I: Creation of a Propaganda Myth |
163 |
Part I: The Labor Theory of Value |
177 |
Part II: The Factory System |
222 |
Part III: The Marxist Propaganda Myth
|
236
|
BOOK II: THE CIRCULATION AND EXPANSION OF CAPITAL Introduction
to Book II: Nonfunctional Definitions, Inflexible Economics, and Criticism
of Smith |
247 247
|
Part IV: Capitalism Without Flexibility |
252 |
Part V: Differing Views of "Capital" and
"Exchange Values"
|
285
|
BOOK III: Profits, Interest, Rent, and Labor Use Values Introduction
to Book III: Making Value Disappear |
306 306 |
Part VI: Profits |
310 |
Part VII: Interest and Returns on Equity Capital |
351 |
Part VIII: Rent |
385 |
Part IX: Economics Based Only On Values Produced
|
396
|
THE GENERAL THEORY by JOHN M. KEYNES |
401 |
Introduction: Keynesian Theory |
401 |
Part I: Labor Market Theory |
409 |
Part II: The General Theory |
418 |
Part III: Interest Rates |
450 |
Part IV: The Business Cycle |
463 |
Part V: Trade Policy
|
482
|
CAPITALISM, SOCIALISM, AND DEMOCRACY |
491 |
Introduction: The Broad Relevance of Schumpeter |
491 |
Part I: Creative Destruction |
498 |
Part II: Socialism |
510 |
INDEX
|
529
|
Publisher’s Introduction:Understanding
of the economic successes and failures
of the past quarter millennium as well as of today begins here. The five books
reviewed and analyzed herein provide the basic theoretical material for
understanding the development of both the capitalist market mechanisms that
have raised billions of people out of subsistence-level poverty, and the
socialist administered alternatives to market mechanisms that flourished and
collapsed so spectacularly during the 20th century after blighting
the lives of billions of people for several generations.[1] Capitalist
market mechanisms are of
course much more than the Middle East bazaars or the village squares on market
day that do little more than facilitate subsistence living. Capitalist markets
are the artificial creation of government and private institutions. By
facilitating commerce, they generate wealth and rising living standards.
Economic evaluation thus must always begin and end with evaluation of the
policies, institutional arrangements and regulatory framework within which the
markets are embedded.[2]
They can either facilitate or fetter the markets. This is the realm of
Political Economy.[3]
Macroeconomic analyses confined to economic factors or their mathematical
representation is inherently incompetent. Socialist
alternatives to market mechanisms
depend on the ability of ministerial arrangements to effectively allocate
scarce resources without market mechanisms or with just minimal assistance
from residual markets. Widespread failure of socialist systems has transformed
socialist beliefs into support for various versions of entitlement welfare
state, commanding heights government enterprise, redistributionist and
industrial policy beliefs. Policies based on these beliefs are all
distressingly confined by market realities that repeatedly impose themselves
through severely diminished economic prospects, rendered especially noticeable
during the business cycle. If
you need or want to know what is actually in these basic books
but lack the time to read some or all of them, these reviews are designed for
you. They also facilitate easy restoration of precise memory for those who
have read the books at some time in the past, or who want to ascertain the
precise location of desired material. They are not “about” the authors or
their times – for which there are already copious sources elsewhere. The
format is based on a half century of experience
providing technical material for busy professionals – lawyers, accountants,
economists, engineers and assorted managerial personnel – willing to pay
substantial sums for accurate, readily accessible concise accounts and
analyses of texts, documents and events. Such professionals have little
patience with factual and analytical weakness or ideological advocacy. The
quality of the analytical comments is supported by a half century of accurate
published economic forecasts. The
format facilitates speed-reading and scanning,
with liberal inclusion of quoted material covering the most important and
widely referenced material. The books covered are: 1.
Adam Smith, “An Inquiry Into the Nature and Causes of the
Wealth of Nations” (five editions published between 1776 and 1789 during
Smith’s lifetime). 2.
David Ricardo, “The Principles of Political Economy and
Taxation” (1817). 3.
Karl Marx,
“Capital (Das Kapital).” (Book I, 1867) (Book II, published by
Frederick Engels, 1885) (Book III, published by Frederick Engels 1894)
(Foreign Languages Publishing House translation). 4.
John Maynard Keynes, “The General Theory of Employment,
Interest and Money” (1936). 5.
Joseph A. Schumpeter, “Capitalism, Socialism, and
Democracy” (1942).
|
The
Wealth of Nations
|
2) Government Economic PolicyThe superiority of market mechanisms over the administered alternatives that may be directed by government, private associations, experts or intellectuals is set forth by Smith with classic clarity. Each individual seeks to maximize his profits or wages by employing himself and his capital in the most valuable way. Regardless of human imperfections and limitations, the expertise that individuals gain concerning their own business and economic needs must inevitably be superior to that of any outsider. Government restraints and other interference with domestic and foreign commerce are both foolish and dangerous. “What is the species of domestic industry which his capital can employ, and of which the produce is likely to be of the greatest value, every individual, it is evident, can, in his local situation, judge much better than any statesman or lawgiver can do for him. The statesman who should attempt to direct private people in what manner they ought to employ their capitals would not only load himself with a most unnecessary attention, but assume an authority which could safely be trusted, not only to no single person, but to no council or senate whatever, and which would nowhere be so dangerous as in the hands of a man who had folly and presumption enough to fancy himself fit to exercise it.”[8] For over 200 years, advocates of mercantilism, communism,
socialism, price controls, protectionism, industrial policy, social
engineering and other administered alternatives have all rejected this wisdom.
They have expended vast and varied efforts to improve on market results —
and have all failed miserably — often with disastrous results that
have blighted the lives of billions of people. Their "folly" was
often vastly dangerous indeed. All too frequently, administered policies are in reality efforts to promote political or personal interests above national interests. Competitive markets — even with competitive conditions that are far from perfect — provide a cornucopia of benefits and easily achieve results superior to the most elaborate administered alternatives. [DB]
|
Principles
|
Capital
(Das Kapital)
|
The propaganda purpose of his book becomes apparent even before it begins. Marx starts right off in his Preface to the second edition by invoking the science propaganda ploy[49] — a common practice for him by that time. After all, who can doubt the word of “science?” However, the approximately one dozen forecasts made in Book I on the basis of Marx’ “scientific investigations” turn out to be almost entirely in error as do all but a couple of the expectations expressed in the other two Books. It is the most basic principle of science that, when forecasts go wrong, something must be amiss with the theory.[50] What could it be? The ridiculousness of this claim to scientific certitude is immediately revealed when Marx — in the same 1873 Preface (during a time of economic recession) — confidently and smugly predicts the imminent end of days of capitalism. This is his first of many fearless faulty forecasts. The bourgeois economy was already “in the time of its decline” in the advanced Western nations. The business cycle was visibly — to Marx — reaching the point of capitalist overproduction where it would produce an economic collapse that would be chronic and catastrophic.[51] “The contradictions inherent in the movement of capitalist society impress themselves upon the practical bourgeois most strikingly in the changes of the periodic cycle, through which modern industry runs. That crisis is once again approaching, although as yet but in its preliminary stage; and by the universality of its theatre and the intensity of its action it will drum dialectics even into the heads of the mushroom-upstarts of the new, holy Prusso-German empire.”[52] Of course, the “mushroom upstarts” would prove to be the Marxists. The last quarter of the 19th century would be a period of unprecedented economic growth and widening prosperity in capitalist nations — and although experiencing periods of intense problems, the 20th century would be much better. Like certain religious sects that are forever expecting the imminent Apocalyptic end of days or the coming of the Messiah, Marxists and some socialists and Keynesian economists — even as late as the 1990s — would stupidly expect every downturn in the business cycle to develop into the predicted chronic depression of “mature capitalism.”[53] So much for scientific certitude! For Marx as for so many other ideologues, reality is perverse. It simply refuses to conform to ideological expectations. Economics is not a “science” in any meaningful sense of that term. It is a nonscientific practical art — requiring a professional analytical approach — like law and accounting and warfare and the delivery of health care — and like politics and sociology — two other fields with pretensions to scientific status. Scientific certitude — something that is not without considerable variability even within those experimental sciences that enjoy broad access to the full scientific method — is the closest to absolute certainty that humans can rationally come. However, the “scientific method” is not broadly available in the nonscientific practical arts. The availability of some useful scientific tools is not sufficient to broadly provide scientific certitude in such fields. The availability of paints and brushes made scientifically by Dupont does not change painting into a “science.” The most that can be expected in these fields is the opinions of professionals. Such professional opinions — when offered by professionals with deep understanding of their fields — can be remarkably reliable — but scientific certainty they cannot provide. Only propagandists — and the ignorant — speak of economics and these other fields as “science.” Karl Marx is, of course, very aware of the propagandistic use of the term “science,” and repeatedly accuses others — especially other socialists — of this propagandistic misuse of the term.[54] There cannot be multiple scientific truths. This pot does not hesitate in calling the kettles “black.” For Karl Marx is here performing propaganda magic. Like Lamont Cranston – “The Shadow” back in the days of radio drama — he is clouding the eyes of the suitably credulous so that obvious aspects of reality seem to disappear. In Das Kapital, the obviously vital productive roles of capitalist commerce and private ownership interests are being rationalized away and made to disappear for a surprisingly large class of suitably credulous people. Many of these people nevertheless pride themselves on being part of an “intellectual elite” — knowledgeable of worldly matters — and capable of taking charge and managing the economy of a communist or socialist system. Most of these true believers never plumb the depths of the caliginous bog of interminable rationalization tedious with detail and repetition — but nevertheless glaringly incomplete — with which Marx blinds their eyes. With the faithful — those that blindly follow Marxism as a secular religion — those ideologically willing to be blinded to reality — Marx succeeds magnificently. |
|
Book III: Profits, Interest, Rent, and Labor Use Values[64]Introduction to Book III:[65] Making Value DisappearMarx finally confronts his fundamental irresolvable problem in Book III. There are numerous processes and incentives in the capitalist system that obviously contribute greatly to its productivity yet don't involve industrial labor. For his propaganda purposes, Marx must disparage them and maintain his view that they contribute no “value.” Of course, he fails. He throws up numerous examples of capitalist abuses and confusing clouds of obscuring detail about the business cycle. This provides much grist for Marx' propaganda mill and an emotional smokescreen with which the weaknesses of Das Kapital are hidden. “Profits”
— frequently now by name — but still frequently
confounded with surplus value — finally comes front and center under
consideration in Book III. Much of Book III is concerned with the relationship
of these two concepts, and with interest and rent — but not ground rent on
raw land — as forms of profit. “Profits” are redefined in Book III to
show its close relationship with surplus value. However, this merely shifts the tendency to confound profits
with surplus value to a tendency to confound “profits” as redefined by
Marx with “profits” as normally defined.[66]
His redefinition of the term reduces it to a concept with No functional
applicability in capitalist economics.
His definitions and redefinitions
of other terms compound this problem. Both Marx and Engels continuously trip
up when applying “profits” as Marx redefines that term to phenomena that
can only be explained by “profits” as normally defined.
Even
worse, with his expanded definition of “profits” Marx is left without any
concept for explaining the maximum rate possible for capital expansion — the
heart and soul of Marx' “scientific investigations.” In Book III, he
illogically equates the “rate of profit” as he defines it with the degree
of self-expansion of capital.[67]
Differences in the productivity of individual capitalists also begin to gain recognition in Book III. Yet, Marx still expects a general collapse. He generally deals with capitalist facilities as homogeneous masses, all of which might collapse together as overproduction and overcapacity squeeze profits. He mentions differences among producers only in passing while discussing other things. He similarly — but just in passing — even provides recognition of the productive importance of the ownership interest — apparently oblivious that this is inconsistent with his continued denial that it contributes to value. Marx’ abstract labor theory of value has no visible impact on individual capitalists or industries, Marx and Engels perforce repeatedly acknowledge. Marx asserts instead that its impacts exist only as broad economic averages for an entire economy. In a desperate tail-wagging-the-dog argument, Marx and Engels assert that these averages somehow determine their constituent parts instead of being, as averages always are, mere dependent variables – mathematical calculations determined by their parts. Very conveniently, these impacts are too attenuated to be demonstrated.[68] His “scientific” hypothesis cannot be tested. Unfortunately for Marx, repeated efforts at demonstrating some functional role for this and his other concepts all clearly fail.[69] Engels considered Book III the most important of the Books of Das Kapital. Book III has more of Engels in it than any other Book, although he assures us that his arrangements, supplementations and additions were all carefully in line with the notes and thoughts of Karl Marx.[70] However, Schumpeter advises caution due to doubts about whether Engels’ contributions and Marx’ notes reflected Marx’ mature considered opinions.[71] In Book III, Marx finally attacks the problem of “profits” directly and aggressively. Supplemented by Engels, he finally deals at length with profits in its varying forms as industrial and mercantile profits, as interest and as rent. With some semantics slight-of-hand, he radically redefines the terms “profits” and “total capital,” and then pretends that they describe the same phenomena as when normally defined.[72] Nevertheless, Book III is the least read — perhaps because it is a daunting 890 pages in length — not counting Engels' usual 20-page Preface. Book IV, produced well after Engels' death, is primarily an account of the history of the theory of surplus value and — mercifully — of so little import as to be readily disregarded. In particular, Marx failed to fulfill his long-standing promise to provide an explanation of financial capital and competitive markets that reconciled their obvious roles in capitalist productivity with the contention by Marx that they added no value to capitalist production. For example, Section 2 of Chapter 6 of Book III begins with the acknowledgement that world markets and the credit system are essential to an understanding of the capitalist system, and provides assurance that they will be covered in the “continuation” of Book III after “the general nature of capital” is explained.[73] Marx does, in fact, herein provide voluminous material on the monetary and financing mechanisms of capitalism and their uses. Yet again, he resorts to a distinction without a difference as his ultimate propaganda ploy. The financial system bestows many “benefits” on the productive and distributional systems, but no “value.”[74] He fails to explain how these financial mechanisms can be so useful — indeed, admittedly essential — and yet not contribute to the “value” created by the system. He hides this failure behind his usual emotional smokescreen by instead passionately and repeatedly emphasizing the abuses and periodic failures of the system. Marx’ view of overhead and commercial activities is similarly in obvious error. As repeatedly pointed out herein, even in the terminology devised by Marx, all activities that contribute to most efficiently bring goods to market must contribute to the value of those goods. The coverage of rents is the most logical part of Das Kapital. It is also the subject with which Marx is most in agreement with Adam Smith. Unlike Smith, however, Marx — as is expected — emphasizes the problems and costs of private ownership of land while disparaging the benefits — indeed, the essentiality — of private property.[75]
|
The
General Theory
|
2) The Influence of Karl MarxIt is evident that Keynes rejected much of the worst of Marxian doctrine. Where Marx naively relies totally on socialist directives,[87] Keynes relies on competitive markets to allocate resources — until that becomes politically inconvenient. Similarly, Keynes tolerates private property rights — as long as that doesn’t get in the way of government plans.[88] Keynes uses market exchange values[89] instead of Marx' impractical concept of industrial labor use-values.[90] Keynes had infinite faith in paper money managed by governments[91] — Marx had none.[92] Keynes can thus omit all of the twisted indeterminate immaterial and nonfunctional definitions and redefinitions of economic terms that Marx relied upon for the defense of his narrow industrial labor use-value concept of commodity values and for support of his propaganda myth.[93] Profits — frequently referred to as “income” or “yields” or “proceeds” — takes its obvious place for Keynes as a determining factor for capitalist economic development. Although he views capitalism as unable to operate at optimal levels for any length of time, Keynes recognizes — unlike Marx — that capitalism is inherently stable within the parameters of the business cycle.[94] Moreover, Keynes avoids many of the weaknesses of logic that permeate Marx' work.[95] Nevertheless, Marx permeates Keynesian theory, and unsurprisingly infuses Keynesian theory with numerous weaknesses and leaves it divorced from reality in numerous ways, as is persistently pointed out at numerous points below. · Marx' “mature capitalism” fallacy — for which Keynes cites Marx with approval — is the central feature of the General Theory,[96] and Keynes relies upon some indeterminate concepts of his own to support his “mature capitalism” theme.[97] In the process, Keynes ignores the particular reasons why particular periods of economic trouble have taken place. Marx at least provides them some recognition but considers them just transitory factors.[98] · Like Marx, Keynes incredibly believes that savers that do not invest their savings create unproductive “hoards” that undermine economic activity. Keynes advises that governments counter the impact of idle savings by “directly organizing investment.”[99] · Like Marx, Keynes points an accusing finger at financial reserves. By accumulating funds for future investments or emergencies, Keynes incredibly fears that the dreaded savings “gap” is expanded and the investments that might fill the “gap” are delayed. Such reserves are incredibly believed to constitute “a drag on employment” during periods of accumulation – “suddenly made good in a lump” when the reserves are expended for the intended investment or emergency.[100] · Like Marx, Keynes views the need for profits as the obstacle rather than as the driving force for generating widespread prosperity.[101] · Like Marx, Keynes views wealth and the consumption of “luxury” goods as increasing the instability of capitalist systems.[102] · Like Marx, Keynes views international trade as of benefit to only the wealthy and the middle classes. Foreign trade imposes burdens on the working classes.[103] · Like Marx and all socialists, Keynes has total faith in the capabilities of government and “community” administered economic systems.[104] He appears totally ignorant of the inherent ineptness of government management. He thus ignores Adam Smith's warnings about the weaknesses inherent in the separation of management from ownership.[105] · Keynes naively agrees with Marx that good management and supervision is always readily available and can be procured simply by offer of suitable compensation.[106] · While Marx offers broad socialist solutions, Keynes offers narrower administered solutions directed at controlling interest rates, directing investment flows, redistributing wealth, and ultimately directing the activities of major business entities.[107] · However, when these interventions ultimately prove insufficient, Keynes, too, advises transition to a socialist system to take over and prevent the collapse of major profitless enterprises.[108] · Like Marx, Keynes incredibly believes that the ownership interest is not an essential element in capitalist productivity. Stock market investors are “functionless.” While residual entrepreneurs would continue to be tolerated, Keynes incredibly agrees with Marx that the entrepreneur will become unnecessary.[109] · Keynes like Marx offers a vision of an impossible socialist utopia to entice the credulous. If a capitalist system is resolutely stimulated pursuant to Keynesian policies, it will generate abundant capital assets — “full capitalization” — so that capital assets are no longer scarce. Then, there would no longer be any need for financiers and rentiers.[110] ·
Like Marx, Keynes assumes that the study of economics is a
“scientific” endeavor. He thus avails himself — or at least succumbs
to — the “science” propaganda ploy that was a central feature in the
propaganda myth created by Karl Marx.[111] |
3) The Savings GapKeynes provides us with psychological propensities and inducements to consume, invest and save. He blames the business cycle and involuntary unemployment on the notion that wealthy nations are “mature” capitalist systems that will inevitably save more than can be profitably invested, leading to periods of economic decline — if not chronic economic decline.[112] Like Marx' concepts, none of this can be measured, and in fact all the evidence is exactly the opposite. Mature — wealthy — capitalist systems require and have lower rates of savings — not higher. As assets accumulate, people and businesses can — and observably do — rely more on their asset wealth than on monetary savings. Their asset wealth supports vast increases in the purchasing power of credit, naturally stimulating both consumption and investment, with profit rates and interest rates sensitively adjusting these flows except when other factors undermine the pertinent markets. Except during the depths of already developed severe depressions, financial intermediaries and the money markets have no trouble quickly putting all savings to work in commerce. As is repeatedly pointed out throughout this examination of Marx, “Das Kapital,” and Keynes, “The General Theory,” there is absolutely no evidence that excess savings play any role in initiating periods of economic distress. In fact, contrary to Keynesian assertions, savings declined substantially in the last full year before the Great Depression — the first decline since WW-I — accompanied by a substantial decline in the number of savings accounts.[113] Banks were still paying 4 percent interest to attract savings for more than a year after the ’29 Crash.[114] The decline in savings rates in the U.S. in recent prosperous times has been notorious for decades.
|
Capitalism,
Socialism, and Democracy
|
2) Socialist ExpectationsJoseph A. Schumpeter was a committed socialist with decades of scholarship in socialist history, practice and theory. “Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy,” the source of his theory of creative destruction in capitalist systems, is thus about socialism, not capitalism.[117] Schumpeter admired Karl Marx as the first to provide a systematic analysis of socialism. Marx was “the one great socialist thinker,” according to Schumpeter.[118] Marx established socialist theory as a principled doctrine attached to a class movement. Marx recognized the working class as “an existing or potential source of social power.” Marx also recognized the favorable tendencies that supported socialism as a serious political factor.[119] Schumpeter thus accepts Marx' theory as “scientific.” However, Schumpeter expressly rejects Marx' doctrine.[120] Admiration did not blind Schumpeter to the glaring weaknesses in many of Marx’ most important doctrinal elements. Schumpeter found many inadequacies in Marx' analytical methodology, including “a long list of conclusions that do not follow or are downright wrong; mistakes which if corrected change essential inferences, sometimes into their opposites.”[121] Schumpeter points out that the labor movement, for one prominent example, is not necessarily socialist and clearly benefits over time from capitalist economic development. Marx, too, is thus revealed to be as utopian as the utopian socialists both Marx and Schumpeter despised. Marx’ theory is mere “ideology,” Schumpeter asserts. It is “unrealistic dreaming.”[122] Since the early trade union movement was viewed during Marx' time as a diversion, and thus a competitor of socialism, communism was then just a movement of squabbling intellectuals.[123] Marx readily acknowledged the productivity of capitalism and thus based his prophecy of capitalist demise precisely on its great productivity. Marx expected that the capitalist drive for capital accumulation and profits would run into a cul-de-sac of overproduction and squeezed profits and ultimately chronic crisis. The result would be an increasingly militant workforce exploited under increasingly harsh working conditions. There would also be an enlarged and militant reserve army of unemployed and underemployed workers that would be ready, willing and able to participate in the triumph of communism.[124] The processes of “creative destruction” undermine Marx’ expectation. Schumpeter explains that competition would continuously drive out the outmoded, the poorly managed and the poorly placed so that profitable capitalist production would always be possible for the survivors and for new capitalist enterprises.[125] Marx' explanation of the ultimate collapse of capitalism is obviously untenable, according to Schumpeter, but capitalism was probably doomed nevertheless.[126] Schumpeter viewed the demise of capitalism as a tentative probability while Marx' viewed it as a “scientific” certainty.[127] It is a central thesis of Schumpeter's book that capitalism will ultimately destroy its own foundations not in its economic evolution but in its sociological evolution. Capitalism would ultimately be undermined not by some inevitable economic collapse but by its continued massive success. It would eventually achieve a “mature capitalism” state of full capitalization and an economic “stationary state” that would lay the groundwork for socialist takeover.[128] “Capitalism is being killed by its achievements.”[129] Sociological and political factors based on envy — “immiserization” — and redistributionist fervor would probably result in a political turn to socialism at some point in the future, Schumpeter explains.[130] He recognizes tendencies favoring socialism already existing in the New Deal government, in its bureaucracy and political classes.[131] Efficiencies of scale of an increasingly concentrated capitalist system would undermine all of the smaller competitors and a mature capitalist system would reach a point of development that left little scope for entrepreneurial activity, facilitating the socialist takeover. He expected innovation to be dominated by the “increasing mechanization of industrial progress (teamwork) in research departments,” leaving little scope for the individual entrepreneur or small innovative enterprise.[132] A segment on creative destruction occupying about one quarter of this book was included by Schumpeter for the purpose of explaining why Marx' expectation of a capitalist collapse due to chronic overproduction and profit squeeze would not come to pass.[133] However, it was communist and socialist systems worldwide that collapsed. These experiments were not benign. They suffered catastrophic failures that blighted the lives of billions of people for several generations during the 20th century.[134] Thus, about three quarters of Schumpeter's “Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy,” are today of apparently little more than historic interest. All that today is left of major significance would seem to be just the segment on the capitalist creative destruction process that keeps competitive capitalism eternally vibrant.[135] For this, Schumpeter is correctly included with Smith and Ricardo in the pantheon of immortal contributors to capitalist theory. Smith did recognize the creative destruction process,[136] but it is Schumpeter who explained it in some detail, emphasized its importance and provided its name. Both communism and socialism achieved widespread often-fervent acceptance among intellectuals in the years between the world wars. These intellectuals were all too often willfully blind to glaring weaknesses. Marxian doctrine had achieved little influence in the U.S. before WW-I.[137] Ultimately, of course, it was the markets that had the last word. Believers whose analytical capabilities were thus revealed to be grossly deficient doggedly kept the faith until brutally mugged by reality. Marx was revealed as a false god. Schumpeter, too, exhibited a total lack of understanding of the infinite possibilities of capitalism and entrepreneurship.[138] In this he was just like Marx and Keynes and so many other left wing intellectuals, and was similarly mugged by reality. It is more than a little ironic that the short creative destruction segment added to explain continued capitalist economic success became the basis for Schumpeter's fame as a theorist of capitalism, while his major work and decades of scholarship on socialist theory is today dead and buried for all but a few economic scholars. Somehow, Schumpeter failed to realize that his creative destruction process must ultimately doom all socialist schemes. The expected “mature capitalism” period of full capitalization and an economic “stationary state” that would lay the groundwork for socialism seemed reasonable during the Great Depression, but was and remains an impossibility.[139] However, the sociological and political processes that Schumpeter expected would lead to a socialist transformation were very accurately described by Schumpeter. These processes continue to be vital factors in the persistent advances of redistributionist fervor and industrial policy, commanding heights government enterprise capitalism, and the entitlement welfare state. The socialist gods— the sociological and political trends explained by Schumpeter— survived the widespread demise of socialism to become the gods of the entitlement welfare state. They thus continue to threaten private enterprise capitalism in the 21st century. For this reason, the bulk of Schumpeter’s "Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy" on socialism actually retains considerable relevancy. |
__________________________________
[1]
See, Joshua Muravchik, "Heaven On Earth, The Rise and Fall of
Socialism," (Encounter Books 2002). |