BOOK REVIEW
Frontiers of Legal Theory
by
Richard A. Posner
FUTURECASTS online magazine
www.futurecasts.com
Vol. 7, No. 10, 10/1/05.
Modern legal theory: |
The legal system of the United States - outside Louisiana
- is a common law legal system. The ways in which judges and the bar have
developed common law rules and procedures - and the policies and principles that
guide this process - are little understood outside the legal profession. & |
This part of the book is predominantly a justification for the expansion of judicial discretion so that the courts can determine and set social policy appropriate for modern conditions. |
In "Frontiers of Legal Theory," Richard
A. Posner, judge on the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit, begins
with an explanation of
how the courts sometimes draw on concepts from other disciplines when
developing new legal rules and procedures or new interpretations of existing
rules and new applications of existing procedures. However, this part of the book is
predominantly a justification for the expansion of judicial discretion so that
the courts can determine and set social policy appropriate for modern
conditions. & |
Economics, psychology, statistical inference, epistemology (the truth finding capacity of legal procedure) are the disciplines examined by the author as distinct but overlapping examples of how concepts developed in other disciplines sometimes impact the law. These are the most prominent disciplines that contribute to modern legal development. The author mentions other fields but does not provide extensive coverage because they tend to be narrow of focus or without significant professional support.
The great increase in the number of law professors - and the growing influence in the law of women and minorities - and the influence of political radicals, "has increased the market for critical, which generally are external, perspectives on the legal system," Posner explains. "And abundant data on the system that are easily retrievable and analyzable are helping to sustain legal theory as a research program." |
|
|
"The legitimacy of a practice by which a committee of judges can check the power of the democratic majority to implement its preferences in law has long been a staple of debate within the legal profession." |
Three main approaches to Constitutional theory are covered by the author.
As a practical matter, the courts are inevitably influenced by the same interest groups that influence the legislative and executive branches. The principles of "public choice" involve agenda setting, "the strategic interactions between different branches of government, and the indeterminacies of voting as a method of aggregating preferences." Game theory and rational-choice models are thus covered by the author. |
In the U.S., the failure of sociological efforts to come up with feasible and credible methods of dealing with crime have marginalized the impact of sociology on the law and is a part of "a general malaise of sociology in American higher education." Nevertheless, sociological studies have contributed greatly to the understanding of the operations and impacts of the legal system.
Theories that view the law in radical feminist or racial terms and postmodern scholarship that emphasizes "the plasticity of the legal system" are outgrowths of critical and postmodern legal studies.
|
|
The basic Constitutional issue of judicial review is introduced by Posner as a prime example of how legal theory inevitably interacts with the law. He asks whether judicial review has on balance been good or bad for political governance under the U.S. system, and reasonably comes up with a host of examples that seem beneficial and others that seem obstructive or harmful.
|
Law and economics:
& |
The relationship of economics and the common law
goes back centuries. Posner refers to contributions by Thomas Hobbes, Jeremy
Bentham, David Hume, Adam Smith. It is a subset of the economics of nonmarket
behavior. It evaluates costs against benefits, expected pleasure against
expected pain. & |
Economic analysis "also tries to improve law by pointing out respects in which existing or proposed laws have unintended or undesirable consequences and by proposing practical reforms." |
The relationship is most evident in fields like antitrust and
public utility regulation dealing with competition and monopoly - the legal
regulation of explicit markets. However, it is also applicable for property,
contracts, taxation, corporations, patents. Bentham applied economic analysis to
crime and punishment.
Economic analysis is used to describe the substance and structure of the system and predict the behavior of participants.
The results have been reforms in fields dealing with the regulation of
various aspects of commerce. Its influence is felt in the calculation of damages
in personal injury suits, the determination of alimony and the division of
property in divorce cases, the determination of fiduciary obligations, and even
in the federal sentencing guidelines. It contributed significantly to the
deregulation movement and the restoration of free market concepts. |
Economic analysis transforms law from an assemblage of unrelated practices, institutions and bodies of law into a deeply coherent structure. |
Economics offers an ideologically neutral analytical method for dealing with politically controversial legal topics, Posner asserts. Ideally, "the economist favors neither side, favors only efficiency." It also frequently "dissolves contentious" situations by demonstrating a fundamental mutuality of interests. Creditor and debtor, buyer and seller, need each other even as they struggle with each other for individual advantage.
Posner demonstrates how economic analysis transforms law from an assemblage of unrelated practices, institutions and bodies of law into a deeply coherent structure. Economic analysis provides reasoned structure to the determination of prudent conduct, the assessing of damages or criminal penalties, and the regulation or deregulation of commercial conduct. Unrelated legal issues frequently involve identical economic issues. Posner provides a prominent example.
Copyright, trademark, and privacy law can be viewed as "ways of
striking the balance between the benefits and cost of recognizing
personality" - a balance similar to that involved in markets for
"credence goods" such as in art markets. |
Economic analysis, of course, does not compel moral judgments, Posner stresses. However, it can motivate a rethinking of moral judgments. For example, workers' rights laws - like ERISA pension guarantees - can on balance hurt workers in the market by reducing employment opportunities, wages, or investment in their skills.
|
The basic job of the economist is to remind us of the consequences that noneconomists tend to overlook, consequences that often though not always are adverse or at least costly, of actual or proposed policies and practices. |
Economics is ostensibly "value neutral" and can be used to critically evaluate conservative - or libertarian - concepts as well as liberal concepts. For example, Posner notes that conservatives would prefer that government pay for "landmark preservation" facades by purchasing an easement in building facades rather than by employing a taking by regulatory designation. However, economic analysis indicates that this is merely a choice of takings since the government doesn't really "pay" for anything. Either the building owners or the taxpayers (or consumers due to inflation) bear the burdens of government takings depending on how the government chooses to act.
Economics "is the science of the consequences of human behavior," Posner stresses.
|
Analysis of free speech issues are rife with "indeterminacies." |
The application of economic analysis to free speech rights cases is Posner's first major example and amply demonstrates the lack of precision in this "science." Posner uses well known examples - the shouting of "fire" in a crowded theater - attempts to obstruct the draft during wartime by distributing leaflets to draftees urging noncompliance - or generalized opposition to war policy. Making use of mathematical reasoning, Posner explains his economic analysis as:
Yet, all of these factors - made to look so precise when presented in
mathematical form - are unknowable in most cases, as Posner readily recognizes.
He recognizes the inapplicability of his mathematical expressions, offering them
only as "a way of framing and thinking" about the regulation of
speech. In clear cases - where the harm is great and likely - the ban will be
upheld without the need for economic analysis. A more nebulous approach will be
taken in closer cases simply by recognizing a preference for free speech. (The
attempt to actually weigh costs and benefits in these cases will be rare - more
often than not just a makeweight argument.) |
Cost-benefit analysis is evident in instances where limitations on
speech are justified as facilitating speech. "Limiting the number of
participants in a televised debate, preventing demonstrators from blocking
traffic, allowing the prohibition of false advertising and providing legal
remedies against copying and defamation are examples."
|
|
Subsidization of counter speech -- such as in anti-smoking, safe sex or patriotic advertising - does not have the same impact as censorship, since people are free to disregard it or accept it at will, and it may be offset by other views.
|
"Americans are awash in superstitious and erroneous, even preposterous, beliefs, in part because of sensationalistic and inaccurate 'news' media; many members of the intelligentsia are dupes of absurd ideas peddled by radical postmodernists; and there is a staggering amount of trash culture, both popular and highbrow."
"[But if consumers of ideas] can't sort out truth from falsity, or beauty from ugliness, in the wares produced in these markets, how likely is it that censors, judges, or juries can?" |
Posner falls back on the traditional method of deciding free speech issues when weighing indeterminate costs and benefits. .
He adopts a tactical view. It is better to fight the battle for free
speech at its outer reaches, where utterly worthless and deeply offensive speech
is all that is at risk, than closer to its core, where controversial material
like "The Bell Curve" or "The Case for Same Sex Marriage"
may be at issue. This also prevents the law from degenerating into whatever the
judges would prefer.
|
Only the market has tools like competition and the test of time to apply to the task of separating value from trash.
Economic analysis is irrelevant to those who see these issues in moral terms, since they are generally blind to the real consequences of actions taken for moral purposes. |
The market in ideas is highly complex - full of externalities - both
benefits and costs, Posner notes. Its outputs - such as truth and beauty - are
not always readily evident and may be different for different consumers. These
must be left to the market in competitive ideas, since only the market has tools
like competition and the test of time to apply to the task.
Posner closes this chapter with brief analyses of efforts to regulate
"hate speech," campaign financing, and the internet. He discusses the
costs and benefits of various regulatory approaches. He has little trouble
demonstrating that the costs of such regulation generally outweigh the benefits.
He readily concedes that this economic analysis is irrelevant to those who see
these issues in moral terms, since they are generally blind to the real
consequences of actions taken for moral purposes. |
Noneconomic values: |
Critics of the extension of economic analysis to
issues that "are not traditionally economic" respond that in many areas efficiency or other economic values are not the primary concerns. |
Economics does not - and does not pretend to - offer utopian outcomes. |
Basic values like freedom or autonomy are not economic. However, economic forms of analysis still have their place in diverse fields of the law, the author counters.
Economics does not - and does not pretend to - offer utopian outcomes. Determining what is the most efficient or productive outcome does not "generate or validate a theory of distributive justice," the author points out. Inequalities of wealth always confer advantages. However, the author believes that the vast majority of people prefer a "common law shaped by wealth maximization."
Posner points out that much wealth inequality is a matter of choice -
of how long or hard to work and what risks to take and what skills to acquire
and jobs to perform. He would have been far wealthier as a practicing attorney
than as an appellate court judge. Much inequality reflects the different stages
of the life cycle. Much reflects innate abilities and health. And much is sheer
luck.
|
Income levels - "a society's average or median income" - are more likely to affect political stability than income distribution, as long as it includes a sizable middle class.
If efforts to reduce inequality undermine the economy or reduce its dynamism, they may actually increase political instability and make it harder for people to rise out of poverty.
Equality of opportunity may thus be a far more important factor for political stability than equality of outcome. |
Social issues involving income inequality are examined by Posner. He easily debunks left wing alarums about inequality and political instability.
As long as a nation is broadly prosperous, Posner points out,
inequality of wealth and the existence of an underclass are unlikely to
undermine political stability. Too many people have a stake in maintaining
lawful conduct. Thus, income levels - "a society's average or median
income" - are more likely to affect political stability than income
distribution, as long as it produces a sizable middle class.
The ability of the poor to rise up the income ladder is what makes the U.S. so attractive to immigrants, most of whom initially occupy the lowest income levels. If efforts to reduce inequality undermine the economy or reduce its dynamism, they may actually increase political instability and make it harder for people to rise out of poverty.
Posner acknowledges dissatisfaction based on concerns about economic
equity or sheer envy. However, he notes the ability of democratic systems to
respond to such pressures by reducing or masking the inequality sufficiently to
maintain stability. Even envy may be readily channeled into constructive efforts
at emulation as long as the economy is healthy and growing. Equality of
opportunity may thus be a far more important factor for political stability than
equality of outcome. |
Application of cost-benefit analysis: |
Cost-benefit analysis is widely recognized as a part of
government decision-making processes. Posner points out that it generally
becomes the predominant process for the wide variety of government decision
making processes that are significantly insulated from interest group influence. & |
Issues of distributive justice are the province of tax and spending policies.
Cost benefit analysis is a valuable input that "compels the decision maker to confront the costs of a proposed action."
The justification for cost-benefit analysis need not include anything more profound than the pragmatic recognition that it increases the chances of observably superior outcomes. |
Cost-benefit analysis is an objective methodology at its best. Applied to the
common law, it relies on a "wealth maximization" criterion. Issues of
distributive justice are the province of tax and spending policies.
Even inept cost-benefit analysis is useful, since the errors arm
litigants that seek to judicially modify or overthrow regulatory actions.
"It is more difficult to challenge a regulation that is based on nebulous
equity grounds." |
Legal precedent and statutory history:
& |
Posner begins his essay on
legal history and its uses with an explanation of the essays on history of
Friedrich Nietzsche. Basically, Nietzsche asserts that history should be
evaluated according to
its uses rather than according to its accuracy. Is history a listing of facts - an understanding of how those facts
developed - or an exercise in mythmaking in support of some societal purpose?
(Those who prefer mythmaking on behalf of some ideological agenda - like Nietzsche
- are always the harshest critics of efforts at the objective analysis of
history.) & |
"With respect to the use of history to guide law," Posner asks whether historic precedent provides templates for resolving current issues - or - a straitjacket that blocks progress? (History does tend to repeat itself in many ways - but never without varying degrees of differences.)
Nietzsche basically criticizes the analysis of history because of the common weaknesses of its practices and the misuses of its results. He bluntly favors mythmaking on behalf of great causes.
While Posner accepts accuracy in historic analysis as a "good," he notes that there are many societal "goods," and that historical knowledge and precedent is not always helpful -- and can be obstructive -- of efforts to achieve them. One notorious example is the way that remembrance of the conflicts and atrocities of the past can get in the way of current efforts at the establishment of peaceful and fruitful relations between peoples.
|
"Judges rewrite history, like Commissars." |
Posner rejects the "purely instrumental" - the Orwellian -
approach to history. However, he asserts that judges use this approach all the
time. "Judges rewrite history, like Commissars." Rather than be in
thrall to history, they bend history "to the service of life," - like Nietzsche.
|
Modern Constitutional law is a pragmatic judicial effort to free the "living" from the rule of the "dead" in behalf of "new solutions" to today's "new problems." |
Modern Constitutional law has descended into a rhetoric of competing myths about Constitutional meanings, Posner explains. He bluntly accepts the fact that modern Constitutional law is a pragmatic judicial effort to free the "living" from the rule of the "dead" in behalf of "new solutions" to today's "new problems." However, since that is the province of the political arms of government, not the judiciary, the courts cloak their efforts in a legal history - in the application of precedent and Constitutional theory - that is increasingly mythological.
|
Law is best regarded "as a servant of social need, a conception that severs the law from any inherent dependence on its past." The only constraint is one of "reason." |
The history of the common law, of course, is anything but rigid. It has always included methods of development and evolution - of new applications to new circumstances. (The new circumstances faced by the colonists in North America resulted in a wide variety of divergences between the law in England and in the colonies and then in the new United States.)
Legislative innovation is, in fact, constrained by Constitutional checks and balances, Posner points out. Statutory law faces difficulties in both enactment and amendment. The Constitution has been made particularly difficult to amend, especially for provisions that are not amenable to changing interpretations. The right to a jury trial in civil cases is still based on a $20 threshold.
According to Posner, law is best regarded "as a servant of social
need, a conception that severs the law from any inherent dependence on its
past." The only constraint is one of "reason." Courts must
explore their reasons for diverging from similar cases in the past, but this is
no more of an imperative than that they explain rejection of "any plausible
potential source of guidance to deciding the present case." |
The reliance interest of business and society in precedent and
past interpretations of statutes is recognized by the author. This reliance
interest justifies the rejection of changes that offer just minimal benefit. He
opposes any "restless experimentation with political and legal
institutions."
|
"Commitment, reliance, information, even inertia are reasons for standing by decisions made in the past." |
In short, legal precedents are only as applicable to current cases as is their reasoning, Posner asserts. Indeed, he recognizes that "commitment, reliance, information, even inertia are reasons for standing by decisions made in the past."
|
Modern originalism is based on its own dubious historical views,
Posner correctly points out. Its dubious use of history, however, misses the
point. Its purpose is "to curb judicial discretion by adopting a mechanical
method of interpretation, one essentially lexicographical and algorithmic rather
than historicist."
However, Posner asserts that precedent should not be "venerated" or applied in cookie cutter fashion to novel issues or issues that are only analogous. When there "is no metric of similarity that will enable a later case to be decided by reference to an earlier one," judge-made law must evolve to deal with the new situation.
|
Political policy setting by the courts: |
Posner's primary objection rests on the indeterminacy of
history. Has history guided judicial decisions, or have judges manipulated
history to support the decisions they preferred? & |
Courts must develop law based on analysis of social policy. |
He easily comes up with several examples of established Constitutional interpretation for which history has been unable to provide a solid basis.
Posner's answer is a frank acknowledgment that courts must develop law based on analysis of social policy. He asks: "Why should the past rule the present?"
|
A chapter debunking exercises in the misuse of legal history and
theory is provided by Posner. He draws on the work of Yale law professors
Bruce Akerman and Paul Kahn.
|
|
As an example supporting his preference for an economic efficiency
approach, Posner discusses differing approaches to the law governing conflicting
claims to the possession of property. Who has the right to unclaimed lost
property - the finder or the owner of a store in which it was found? There are
similar problems of joint possession - future rights - rights to intellectual
property to which many may have contributed - abandoned property - bona fide
purchasers of stolen property (a particularly timely subject with respect to stolen
art) -
and much more that the law must deal with.
Modern law should be shaped to fulfill the social needs of the present - like economic efficiency - rather than held in a strait jacked of existing rules, Posner asserts. Economic analysis provides an objective method for defining a particular social need - for economic efficiency - applicable across many fields of law.
|
"Hate crime" legislation: |
A brief but well nuanced discussion of emotion -
its multifaceted
nature, and its wide variety of impacts relevant to legal issues - is provided by
the author. This sets the stage for his explanation of why he believes that
"hate crime" legislation is an error. & |
The
relevance of various emotional factors is discussed by Posner with respect
to the criminal law objectives of deterrence and confinement. Sometimes, emotions make a criminal more
dangerous - as with serial sex offenders and serial killers - often one and the
same. Sometimes, emotions indicate that a criminal is less dangerous - as when
he acted only in response to provocation. & |
"Hate crime" legislation is the injection of identity politics into the criminal law. |
How, then, should the standard "hate crimes" legislation
be evaluated? Posner argues that hate crime legislation is at best
unnecessary and at worst unwise. It is the injection of identity politics into
the criminal law.
Moreover, the legislation inevitably punishes thought, not action.
|
Ideology and interest-group politics have no proper place in a criminal justice system. In rejecting this precept the supporters of hate crime laws are playing with fire. |
The Supreme Court decision upholding hate crime legislation is criticized by the author. This type of "vague and coarse-grained justification for punishing opinions" is usually rejected by the Court.
|
Emotions and the law:
& |
The criminal law responds to many other factors besides the
social policies of deterrence and prevention and appropriate response to harm
caused, Posner acknowledges. One such factor is moral outrage. Under modern
Supreme Court procedural requirements, moral outrage plays a significant role in
the infliction of capital punishment. On a less lofty note, it plays a role in
the punishment of cruelty to animals. & |
The unemotional application of economic analysis is actually empathetic, because it highlights "the consequences of the litigation" for those not present in the courtroom. |
"Shaming penalties" and victim impact statements in sentencing procedures are analyzed by Posner in similar utilitarian manner. He defends the use - indeed, the necessity - of indignation and empathy in the decision making processes of judges and juries. Without a sense of the widespread indignation that led to the enactment of laws based on aspects of morality, judges and juries could not make sense out of rules against nudity or urinating or intercourse in public, mistreatment of animals, intercourse with beasts or corpses, polygamy, and such.
Indeed, the unemotional application of economic analysis, Posner
asserts, is actually empathetic, because it highlights "the consequences of
the litigation" for those not present in the courtroom. "Future
victims" are of concern whether in sentencing murderers or enforcing
landlord rights or evaluating tax laws. |
Behavioral law and economics: |
Modern criticism of market theory
that attacks its reliance on a hypothetical "rational man" must
perforce be confronted by the author. He points out that these critics - the
"behavioral economists" - offer only explanations, but no usable
theory that might take the place of rational choice economic theory. & |
Explanation and prediction are two different things.
"Describing, specifying, and classifying the empirical failures of a theory is a valid and important scholarly activity. But it is not an alternative theory." |
The critics fail to provide any alternative analytical method or improvements that better explain how markets work. Their concepts have no predictive power. "Explanation and prediction must not be confused."
|
The preferred alternatives of the behavioralists to market solutions frequently rely on the use of "experts," but "the expert, too, is behavioral man" and is just as likely to behave in unpredictable and even irrational ways. |
There are many methodological weaknesses in behavioral economics. The
author notes that university students typically comprise the principal subjects
of experiments in behavioral science - an obvious weakness in methodology. He
handily shreds the validity of a variety of the experiments used by the
behavioralists. |
Finding the facts:
& |
A utopian pure search for truth is beyond the
capacity of any human judicial process. In the real world, costs are very real
constraints. Posner applies his mathematical analytical methods to demonstrate
how benefits must be weighed against costs - broadly defined - and justified in
relation to the importance of the outcome. & |
"Accuracy in adjudication is an economic as well as a moral and political value." |
The benefits include not just the likelihood of finding the truth, but also such factors as the public confidence in the legal system, the deterrence of breaches of criminal and civil law, and the avoidance of the harm caused by erroneous results.
Of course, the importance of a case may be different for private
parties than for the state and society as a whole - something that becomes
apparent in the way private litigants and the state may handle some particular
litigation. Importance also varies between criminal and civil cases - typically
reflected in differing burdens of proof. |
The U.S. does use inquisitorial systems for its administrative agencies. |
The performance of the adversarial system in the U.S. is
compared by Posner with that of the inquisitorial systems in other countries. He
provides an interesting summary and evaluation of various aspects of the
adversarial system and trial by jury. The U.S. does use inquisitorial systems
for its administrative agencies. These have not been free from fairly widespread
dissatisfaction with their results.
|
While admittedly far from perfect, the jury system works well.
Unfortunately, it is the odd instances of miscarriage of justice that get the publicity.
|
|
But that does not mean that it is always the best system available.
Jury trials are certainly more time consuming and expensive. Most jury trials
are for criminal law and tort cases. Other types of cases are frequently tried
before a judge without a jury. Many private parties opt for arbitration before
lay judges with relevant expertise, but these are predominantly contract cases.
|
The Ninth Circuit:
The book is in many respects a potpourri of only vaguely related professional intellectual concerns of the author. |
There is much more in this book that is of
interest, but primarily for scholars and those with professional interest in
the law. Posner provides similar analyses of the rules of evidence used in jury
trials - including the "harmless error" rule and some of the problems
involved in determining whether evidence is admissible or inadmissible. He also
evaluates the uses of "citations analysis" for legal studies. & The book is in many respects a potpourri of only vaguely related professional intellectual concerns of the author. & |
The ongoing controversy over the performance of the huge Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals is also analyzed by Posner using a variety of statistical tests. These involve rates of unanimous reversal that thus obviously don't involve ideological differences with the current Supreme Court - rates of summary reversal - and rates of citation by courts in other circuits that are not obliged to follow Ninth Circuit rulings. His conclusion is that the quality of Ninth Circuit work is at or near the bottom for the federal circuits, but that this is apparently due more to the size of the 28 judge court than to ideology or accidents of appointment. The next largest circuit has 17 judges.
|
Please return to our Homepage and e-mail your name and comments.
Copyright © 2005 Dan Blatt