NOTICE: FUTURECASTS BOOKS
Available at Amazon.com
"Understanding the Economic Basics &
Modern Capitalism: Market Mechanisms and Administered
Alternatives" Smith:
Wealth of Nations. Ricardo: Principles.
|
CAPITAL (DAS KAPITAL) (Vol. 1)
by
Karl Marx
(Britannica Great Books translation)
Part I: Value Determined by an Abstract Labor Standard
FUTURECASTS online magazine
www.futurecasts.com
Vol. 5, No. 10, 10/1/03.
Karl Marx: |
Volume 1, Part II: "Contradictions in Capitalist Industrialization." |
Volume 2, Part III: "The Circulation & Expansion of Capital." |
Introduction to Vol. 1, Parts I & II
Economic value:
& |
Of those who have
waded through "Das Kapital," few - especially among the
"Marxists" - had the economic knowledge to
evaluate it. Indeed, very few who call themselves
"Marxists" - it is widely acknowledged - have ever bothered to
even read Karl Marx. This is quite understandable. & |
The rationalizations begin with a tautology - contain major blatant contradictions - are permeated with distinctions that don't reflect any differences - and are based on definitions and redefinitions of economic terms that are indeterminate, completely without function in the real economy, and applied in slipshod and clearly inappropriate fashion. |
Volume 1 of Das Kapital is 383 small print - densely
paragraphed pages in the Britannica Great Books translation. It is composed
of tediously interminable, repetitively and minutely detailed rationalizations,
that are nevertheless obviously incomplete and irrational. About 100
pages are dedicated to presenting the undoubted horribles of economic life in
the 19th century and in the several centuries prior to that period.
|
Das Kapital is full of obvious important internal inconsistencies, a basic reliance on tautological reasoning, numerous distinctions without practical difference, bald denials, selective - one hand clapping - analyses of causation, semantics games based on sly and nonfunctional definitions and redefinitions of terms, and a host of omitted essential factors.
Even Marx, although working feverishly on Das Kapital for about three decades, ultimately found it impossible to work logically with his own ideas. |
There are obvious answers to this narrow Marxist view of the labor theory of value and the expectation of chronic capitalist crisis.
Adam Smith evenhandedly recognized both the abuses
and economic contributions of industrialists, financial institutions and merchants - with explanations
that are both brief and remarkably clear. See, Adam Smith,
"The Wealth of Nations," (Part I - "Market Mechanisms"). Karl Marx, on the other hand, created a dense rationale for
emphasizing the undoubted abuses and arguing that all the contributions of the capitalist
ownership interest and capitalist financial systems are of no value and can thus
be dispensed with. |
The labor definition of value is exclusive because other things of value in the market don't meet it. Things of value that don't involve industrial labor have no value because they don't involve industrial labor. |
Glaringly omitted from the Marx definition of economic
value are all the factors that contribute to economic production of goods
and services but that have no direct relation to labor on commodities as defined
by Marx. Marx
perforce recognizes a few of these omissions - things that are bought and sold
in the market - things that have a market price - like honor and conscience. Quite
unscientifically - and in this instance with remarkable brevity - buried in the bowels of the
book - he has recourse to a tautology.
Late in Volume 3, Marx notes in a single sentence
that works of art and such are not a part of these "scientific
investigations." |
After all, who needs all those management processes of capitalism if they can all be replaced simply by the issuance of communist directives? |
Two centuries of socialist experiments at all levels would fail abysmally because of their inability to efficiently function without such factors.
With incredible naïveté, Marx - and the
Marxists that came after him - would assume that socialist systems would
solve all their managerial problems simply by employing managers and issuing appropriate directives.
As Schumpeter acknowledges, they can always back up their directives by terror
and the use of force. See, Schumpeter "Capitalism,
Socialism, and Democracy,"
at segment on "The road to
serfdom." After all, who needs all those
management processes of capitalism if they can all be replaced simply by the
issuance of socialist directives? |
Marx commits the ultimate sin in economics - he is not practical. Any concept of value that cannot be accurately and readily calculated is useless for the fundamental purpose of allocating scarce resources.
Marx is attempting to clap with just one hand. True, that one hand is responsible for the clapping - but not alone - or even predominantly. And worse - Marx offers just half a hand - omitting for his propaganda purposes major factors even on the supply side. |
However, the impracticality of the Marxist abstract labor standard would be the most damaging weakness. For all his dense explanations:
Economics, after all, is a practical art
by which scarce resources are allocated. Marx commits the ultimate sin
in economics - he is not practical. Any concept of value that
cannot be accurately and readily calculated is useless for the
fundamental purpose of allocating scarce resources. |
Propaganda myths:
& |
Rationalization is not reason! Das Kapital is a massive exercise in rationalization almost entirely devoid of reason. It is useful only as a propaganda myth, at which it proved spectacularly successful. Nevertheless, many of the most important elements of Marx propaganda myth continue to be widely accepted and remain relevant into the 21st century. |
A) The "Science" Propaganda Ploy
Pseudo science:
& |
The propaganda purpose of this book
becomes apparent even before it begins. Marx starts right off in his Preface to
the second edition by invoking the science propaganda ploy - a common practice
for him by this time. After all, who can doubt the word of "science?" & |
Marx predicts the imminent demise of capitalism. |
However, the approximately one dozen forecasts made in this book on the basis of its "scientific" theories turn out to be almost entirely in error. It is the most basic principle of science that when forecasts go wrong, something must be amiss with the theory. What could it be?
Within the three books, approximately 1800
pages, of Das Kapital, Marx did manage to get some things right. Most important,
Marx recognized the working class as an existing or potential source of social
power. Marx also provided a theory of concentration
foretelling the consolidation of the great industrial giants that would blossom
towards the end of the 19th century, and the social situation they were bound to
create.
|
|
Economics is a nonscientific practical art - requiring a professional analytical approach.
Karl Marx is very aware of the propagandistic use of the term "science," and repeatedly accuses others - especially other socialists - of this propagandistic misuse of the term. |
|
In Das Kapital, the obviously vital productive roles of capitalist commerce and private ownership interests are being rationalized away and made to disappear. |
|
B) The Labor Theory of Value
The "value" of commodities: |
Identification of
the "socially recognized standards of measure" of useful objects
in commerce - of commodities - is the problem with which Marx begins this
work. & |
For the determination of the magnitude of value by labor time, Marx creates a "uniform labour power" standard - "human labour in the abstract" - based on homogeneous, simple, unskilled, subsistence wage labor. |
Market exchange values are stated in constantly
fluctuating sums of money or in barter commodities as defined by the market without
any concern for the use values of the items - although the fact that the items
have use value is inherent in their marketability. Market exchange values are
also unconcerned with the particular labor involved in bringing items to market
- but labor is clearly a major factor affecting market exchange values. In the
market, all goods "are reduced to one and the same sort of labour, human
labour in the abstract." |
"The labour time socially necessary is that required to produce an article under the normal conditions of production, and with the average degree of skill and intensity prevalent at the time." |
Marx thus must create an abstraction - an objective labor standard of value - both for propaganda purposes and as an alternative to capitalist market exchange values.
This requirement that labor be "socially necessary" is especially important, because it is the only objective factor that ties the narrow industrial labor concept of "value" to the market. This factor must be constantly kept in mind since Marx persistently violates it, as will be persistently demonstrated herein. However,
these "values" are constant - rigid - changeable only slowly over long
periods with changes in the industrial factors of production - and totally
unresponsive to the wishes of consumers. Actual day-to-day
conditions in the market have no impact on values. They only affect the extent
to which such values can be "realized" in terms of money.
Marx, of course, is fully aware of the functioning of
capitalist markets. How capitalists are dominated by the forces of market
competition is a pervasive theme in Das Kapital. Substitution effects apply even
for necessities. Consumption can vary over time even for necessities.
Numerous direct contradictions arise throughout Das Kapital because of this obvious requirement that labor be "socially necessary." This becomes painfully clear in Volume 2 when Marx tries to dismiss as "an illusion" all value dependent on commercial activities that don't directly involve the industrial laborer. See, Karl Marx, Capital (Das Kapital) (vol. 2 Part III), "The Circulation and Expansion of Capital," and Karl Marx, Capital (Das Kapital) (vol. 2 Part IV, "Criticism of Smith's Definition of Capital."
|
Homogeneous commodities all are measured by the same kind of value regardless of the actual labor employed in bringing them to market. |
Marx then must define "commodity."
Thus, homogeneous commodities all are measured by the same kind of "value" regardless of the actual labor employed in bringing them to market. They "are only definite masses of congealed labour time." They embody not just utility, but also value for exchange for other commodities.
|
The abstract labor standard is "human labour pure and simple" that need only be defined in units of time for purposes of the calculation of values.
When coats are exchanged for linen, the exchanged items clearly have different values in use, but they have the same value in exchange - which is measured by Marx in equivalent amounts of "labour in its abstract character." |
To make his labor standard "homogeneous,"
Marx reduces it to its lowest common denominator - "unskilled, simple
labor." This is "human labour pure and simple" that need only be
defined in units of time for purposes of the calculation of values. |
Marx recognizes the magic of the market. In the bargain,
each party gives up a value -
which the bargain makes objectively determined - and receives use value - which
remains subjective within the recipient. Absent mistake, the values given up -
the abstract labor values - are equivalent. Not so the use values.
However, in terms of labor value, there is no gain, for
they have given value for value. |
|
The labor that creates one type of commodity "stands expressly revealed as labour that ranks equally with every other sort of human labour."
It is the magnitude of value that controls exchange proportions. |
For barter economies, a value relationship must be
calculated between each commodity and all other commodities in trade. Each
isolated exchange results in a "different elementary expression" of
value that must be repeated for each of the numberless commodities in the
economy. Here it is revealed that value "in its true light" is just
"a congelation of undifferentiated human labour." |
The money commodity: |
Money begins to come into existence
when the value of all
other commodities is expressed when exchanged for one particular
commodity. & |
The money commodity becomes the universal equivalent. |
Marx carves this process up into four distinct steps, which he explains in tedious length.
As soon as a particular commodity is designated to fulfill this role, we have money.
With the advent of a money commodity, in order for each commodity to express its value simultaneously in terms of all other commodities, it must refer to the same equivalent as used by all other commodities. The money commodity becomes "the universal equivalent."
The "undifferentiated human labour" in the
money commodity is the equivalent of that in all other commodities. It becomes
"the social résumé of the world of commodities." That the labor is
"human labor constitutes its specific social character." In the
19th century, the money commodities were metallic - most widely gold and silver. |
Social fictions: |
Commodities thus manifest both perceptible utility
in use, and imperceptible value in exchange. & |
"[With commodities], the value relation between the products of labour, which stamps them as commodities, have absolutely no connection with their physical properties and with the material relations arising therefrom. There it is a definite social relation that assumes, in their eyes, the fantastic form of a relation between things." |
For Marx, this value in exchange is a fantastical relation between things and other things and between all these things and man - a figment of the human mind - much like the religious imaginings of gods, and the imaginings of interactions among gods and between man and the gods.
|
"The equalization of the most different kinds of labour can be the result only of an abstraction from their inequalities, or of reducing them to their common denominator, viz., expenditure of human labour power in the abstract." |
In the production of commodities, human labor, too, takes on a
social character. This social character does not show itself, however, until the
products of that labor - the commodities that were produced - are exchanged in
the market.
|
"The determination of the magnitude of value by labour time is therefore a secret, hidden under the apparent fluctuations in the relative values of commodities." |
Marx presents the labor theory of value as a great discovery - a discovery begun by economists like Smith and Ricardo, but only brought to completion by Marx - a discovery equivalent to that of laws of nature like gravity. That it is hidden behind the money form of values serves to conceal "the social character of private labour, and the social relations between the individual producers."
To begin his attack on the bourgeois form of production, Marx
provides an account of other forms of production in history and in
contemporaneous societies. The "fantastical" bourgeois form is neither a law of nature nor immutable. |
The impact of economic exchange:
& |
Commodities become commodities by
their exchange. By exchange, they both achieve exchange value for the
provider and use value for the purchaser. Only by exchange does the labor spent
upon them prove itself "useful for others." Indeed, "the labour
spent upon them counts effectively only in so far as it is spent in a form that
is useful for others." & |
Because of the market economy and money, the relations of producers "to each other in production assume a material character independent of their control and conscious individual action." |
Property rights are an essential feature of exchange. In tribal
communities, where all property was held in common, exchanges occurred only at
the margins, between one tribe and another with the property each community
owned. However, as soon as such exchanges turn property into commodities, they
are viewed as such for internal intercourse as well. "What makes them
exchangeable is the mutual desire of their owners to alienate them" to
acquire the "foreign objects of utility" that they can be exchanged
for.
The proportions with which they are exchanged is dependent on the
labor in their production. Custom soon "stamps them with values of
definite magnitude." These values come to be measured in relation to the
money commodities - in the 19th century, gold and silver. These appear to become
even in their raw form "the direct incarnation of all human labour."
|
Money and the circulation of commodities:
& |
Thus, the riddle of money is "the most glaring form" of the
riddle of commodities. Marx reviews the various roles played by
money.
1) Money is the measure of value of all other commodities.
Marx cites the price fluctuations of gold and silver bullion. The
impossibility of separating gold and silver money from the impacts of those
fluctuations is proof of the continued relationship between money and its
commodity form. |
2) Money is also the standard of price because it can be
divided accurately into particular units - for silver, into pounds and ounces.
However, because of centuries of debasement by kings and princes, nothing in
fact remains of the original weights of coins but the names. These now
artificial names become the money of account for fixing the value of an
article in its money form. See, "Money is the measure of account,"
below. & |
Market price is usually only an approximate - seldom an exact or "ideal" - measure of "value" as defined by reference to the abstract labor standard. |
However, prices fluctuate sometimes with great volatility.
Price thus is not necessarily an accurate reflection of social labor value.
Prices may be set either too high or too low in comparison with the value of the
social labor represented by the product.
There is no necessary relationship between magnitude of value and price. Indeed, deviations between the magnitude of value and price are more than just possible - they are "inherent in the price form itself." However, this is perfectly proper, since the "apparently lawless irregularities" of the pricing system "compensate one another" by fluctuating about a mean level. Market price is usually only an approximate - seldom an exact or "ideal" - measure of value.
|
An object may have a price without having value. The price in that case is imaginary, like certain quantities in mathematics." |
Marx, himself, is repeatedly forced to have recourse to market
price as the measure of value for his examples.
When exchanges take place, "the price realized may be abnormally above or below the value." Social labor value is the "hidden regulator" and remains ideally somewhere at the mean price level around which the forces of supply and demand cause prices to fluctuate. However, the ideal is not the reality, and even mean price levels differ somewhat from social labor value. Somewhat inconsistently, Marx recognizes that social labor value must change in response to some of the influences that cause those price fluctuations - conditions of overproduction or underproduction - glut or scarcity.
|
Marx is, of course, aware of inflation and its affect on prices.
Substantial new supplies of precious metals are flowing in from newly discovered
mines - and the metal in the coins is being clipped or allowed to be worn away.
However, for the purposes of this analysis, he reasonably assumes a fixed
valuation for the monetary metal - as in the short run it generally has. & |
The seller who receives money may not necessarily expend it again - he may take it out of circulation - he may hoard it - producing "a crisis" if too many hold too much overly long. |
3) Money is the medium of exchange. It is the measure of exchange
value. Marx goes on in extraordinary length to show how the money commodity - as
the medium of exchange - facilitates an endless string of transactions involving
the purchases and sales of goods in commerce - "the circulation of
commodities."
But this string is not foreordained to continue. Whereas, in barter, two different commodities are immediately exchanged for their use value to the new possessors, money breaks this necessary connection. The person who receives the money may not necessarily expend it again - he may take it out of circulation - he may hoard it - producing "a crisis" if too many hold too much overly long.
|
This process of "crisis" is explained by Marx in terms of his pseudo scientific gibberish - of "contradictions" and "thesis" and "antithesis" - by which he attempts to reduce the complex and inherently indefinite logic of economic analysis to a formulaic method with pretensions to scientific certitude.
At this point of the analysis, crisis is merely possible. Its
inevitability is explained by analysis of further elements of the capitalist
economic system, which Marx of course repeatedly emphasizes. |
Marx then gives his views on the velocity of money as currency, in another typical tediously long segment. His views, as with those of Adam Smith, depend on the money having an intrinsic value - as when it was based on precious metals. Thus, the amount and velocity of money in circulation is determined by the amount and prices of commodities. It is economic law "that the quantity of the circulating medium is determined by the sum of the prices of the commodities circulating, and by the average velocity of currency."
|
|
Marx asserts that paper money can have no value unless it is pegged to gold or other precious metal.
Even when paper money is tied to gold, Marx asserts that it can circulate only within the state where it is enforced as a contract. |
More to the point, the notion that paper money can function on the basis of scarcity alone - without any relation to a monetary commodity - is disparaged by Marx. "Only in so far as paper money represents gold, which like all other commodities has value, is it a symbol of value." In predicting that fiat paper legal tender money will prove unsustainable, Marx makes his second major forecasting error of this volume.
Even when paper money is tied to gold, Marx states that it can circulate only within the state where it is enforced as a contract. "This compulsory action [as legal tender] of the State can take effect only within that inner sphere of circulation which is coterminous with the territories of the community."
|
4) Money can be hoarded, as a store of value. "The desire to
hoard is in its very nature insatiable."
However, he recognizes that hoarding vanishes "as a distinct mode
of acquiring riches - - - with the progress of civil society."
Nevertheless, it is replaced by a need for reserves for periodically settling
debt obligations. This need exists at all levels - from the personal to the
national to the international. However, as Marx notes, such reserves - such
hoards - earn nothing. They are "dead stock." The logic of capitalism
is thus to keep money reserves - money hoards - to a minimum. |
|
5) Money is a measure of account, the means of calculating the
amount of credit extended and the means ultimately of satisfying the resulting
debt. By means of credit, the process of exchange need not be instantaneous.
Payment can be made some time after receipt of the purchased commodities.
For major business operations, institutions have been
created to
settle such accounts against each other, so that money need only be provided to
the extent the accounts do not cancel out. |
Sophisticated systems for extending and clearing credit have a
habit of breaking down catastrophically - causing panic that suddenly destroys
credit and reduces all transactions to those that can be arranged with hard
cash. There is a "money famine." This sudden destruction of financial
purchasing power - the sudden collapse of credit - greatly contracts economic
activity. As Marx notes, even in the 17th century it was observed that: "The poor stand still,
because the rich have no money to employ them, though they have the same land
and hands to provide victuals and clothes as ever they had." |
|
Marx asserts the superiority of systems that rely on in-kind payments. |
Marx
ventures two more confident predictions - both of a minor nature - the fourth and fifth
faulty fearless forecasts for Marx in this volume - based on his "scientific" understanding of
economics. He professes confidence in the
"ancient forms of production" that are not dependent on money. He
predicts continued strength for the Ottoman Empire if it can avoid shifting from
payments in kind to money payments for rents and taxes, and he predicts
financial disaster for Japan's small agricultural units if Japan shifts to money
rents from rents in kind.
|
The creation of capital: |
When money buys commodities not for use but
for resale, the commodities become capital, and the holder a capitalist. & |
The objective is not personal use, but monetary gain. Money is not used to gain commodities - it is commodities that are used to gain money - the embodiment of exchange value. In the latter case, the money isn't spent, it is merely "advanced." Marx is variously inconsistent on this point. At certain points, he insists that capitalist production doesn't begin until enough workers are employed so that the capitalist can be freed from all manual labor. Only then do we get "capitalists" and "capital." "This point coincides with the birth of capital itself." Before then, employers are just "small masters." At other times, however, he views even merchants and moneylenders who may have no employees or few employees as capitalists greedily growing their capital.
Each purchase of commodities for use is an independent
transaction. Succeeding transactions require the addition of labor value to
provide new commodities. |
Since the commodity still retains its original labor value, the gain by merchants is "surplus value." In terms of adding labor value to commerce, merchant transactions are meaningless.
These merchant transactions thus boil down to the exchange of capital for capital for more capital - the equivalent of trading money for money for more money - devoid of any addition of labor value to account for the surplus value this process produces. |
However, merchant transactions - the purchase of commodities for resale at a profit - when successful - provides monetary gains and permits "interminable" transactions without any addition of labor value. Advancing money to gain money is mere speculation - a gamble. "More money is withdrawn from circulation at the finish than was thrown into it at the start." Since the commodity still retains its original labor value, the gain is "surplus value." In terms of adding labor value to commerce, merchant transactions are meaningless.
The object of the capitalist is not consumption, but constant gain.
The commodities, themselves, are no longer viewed as use values, but as exchange values - just like money. Such commodities are capital - just like money. These transactions thus boil down to the exchange of capital for capital for more capital - the equivalent of trading money for money for more money - devoid of any addition of labor value to account for the surplus value this process produces.
|
The industrialist and the creditor are not really any different from
the merchant, even though the steps of the transaction are more complex in the
former instance and more direct - money advanced to gain money plus surplus
value - in
the latter. |
The merchant's markup "can only have its origin in the twofold advantage gained, over both the selling and the buying producers, by the merchant who parasitically shoves himself in between them." |
Marx blindly - determinedly - denies that commerce adds value - again relying on the faulty premises about what is and is not value. In the Marxist world, the retail buyer and the producers of commodities could just as easily have met in the market place without the intervention of a merchant and without adding the merchant's profit to the transaction.
However, in Volume 3, when Marx deals with these subjects
specifically, he is forced to recognize some of the many obvious benefits of
these commercial factors. Nevertheless, he retains his view that they add no
value - they just help in the process of "realizing" value already
created by industrial labor power. (This is more tautological
reasoning and distinctions without a difference.)
|
The interest revenues of money lenders are even more blatantly parasitic, since they draw surplus value directly from one party in return for nothing of value - in terms of the standard of value of social human labor in the abstract - which Marx continues to invoke as the sole legitimate measure of value in order to reach this whole series of absurd conclusions.
|
Wage Labor:
Wage labor is labor sold as a commodity - a
phenomenon of the capitalist system. |
Labor can also be sold like a commodity if sold for a particular
purpose and time. If sold totally, it becomes slavery. The laborer must sell his
labor because he lacks the implements and materials with which to produce for
sale the commodities he produces for his employer. |
The average exchange value of basic, unskilled labor power at subsistence wage levels sufficient to maintain the laborers and the families from which the next generation of laborers will come is referred to by Marx - as by Adam Smith - for his calculations. The acquiring of skills involves additional labor, and so has a higher value that generally commands a higher price, but which can be measured in terms of the undifferentiated human labor standard. (Try making such a calculation for yourself - without the assistance of market prices.)
|
|
Since laborers provide their labor for a period of time - a week or two or a month - prior to payment, the employer receives use value prior to payment. |
Since laborers provide their labor for a period of time - a
week or two or a month - prior to payment, the employer receives use value prior
to payment. Laborers are thus obliged to extend credit to their employers. A
bankruptcy can deprive them of their wages. Having no reserves, they are obliged
to buy their immediate needs on credit or from high priced company stores. |
The rate of exploitation: |
"Labour uses up its material factors,
its
subject and its instruments, consumes them, and is therefore a process of
consumption," Marx acknowledges. & |
The profit comes from paying for labor according to its abstract social labor standard value, but keeping the laborer working long enough to provide a greater sum of use value for the capitalist. |
The capitalist efficiently acquires and maintains both the factors of production and the necessary labor - "with the keen eye of an expert." Labor - raw labor power - is to him a thing that he possesses - a use value - like all the other factors of production. His manager and supervisor add the value of their labor to the process. He has a personal interest in everything.
The product of this process is commodities that are use values. But to the capitalist, they are mere "depositaries of exchange-value" - part of his capital. If he can sell them for more than the costs of production, he earns profit and his capital grows. The profit comes from paying for labor according to its abstract social labor standard value - based on subsistence wages - but keeping the laborer working long enough to provide a greater sum of use value for the capitalist - to be incorporated in more commodities for sale - enough to cover all the costs of production and more - a profit - which is thus acquired from surplus value.
|
The capitalist ownership interest has added nothing of value to the process, Marx again somewhat inconsistently asserts, since the costs of production include the costs of managers and supervisors. Marx then claims that this process as he describes it in no way violates "the laws that regulate the exchange of commodities."
As Marx earlier admits, producers who try to sell their commodities for more than labor value will find their customers going elsewhere and will eventually be left without compensation. Price can fluctuate - but it cannot remain above "value" on average more than temporarily.
While Marx at one point suggests that the capitalist interest can be totally divorced from management and supervision, in a couple of brief instances - like the one quoted in the second paragraph of this segment, above - he lets slip his acknowledgement that it is the capitalist that supplies the care, management and supervision that makes the process work. Marx often seems to acknowledge that the capitalist must in fact add entrepreneurial skills for best results. "That a capitalist should command on the field of production is now as indispensable as that a general should command on the field of battle." other points, Marx acknowledges that the profit motive of the ownership interest provides the capitalist with the incentive to make sure that the work is done properly. But to Marx, profits nevertheless add no value to production.
|
|
|
Propaganda magic: On these faulty premises, Marx will perform his great magic trick - and make economic reality disappear from before the eyes of his true believers. |
On the basis of such faulty premises, Marx thus goes on for
hundreds of pages drawing his absurd conclusions about surplus value. They are
absurd not just for their weaknesses of logic, but also because of the obvious
manner in which they are divorced from reality. The errors
are numerous and obvious - for those with eyes to see. |
Unused capital is dead capital, and constantly depreciates. Workers do the employer a favor by working with his assets - bringing them back to life - and providing the wherewithal for their maintenance. |
Marx must disparage the capitalist's role as provider of the
tools and wherewithal of production if he is to achieve his propaganda purposes. So, he
turns this activity on its head, and instead emphasizes the employee's role in
providing the wherewithal - the use-value of his labor - to maintain the
capitalist's capital. Unused capital is dead capital, and constantly depreciates. Workers do
the employer a favor by working with his assets - bringing them back to life -
and providing the wherewithal for their maintenance. |
Marx is not exactly consistent in what labor adds or does not add value. At the end of Volume 3, we learn that bookkeepers are very important. Indeed, in communist systems, they will be extremely important, since it is they who will have to evaluate and keep track of all these indeterminable "values" that will supposedly govern the communist system. Once the capitalist system is superseded, bookkeeping processes on a vast and complicated scale encompassing the ascertaining of "values" "becomes more essential than ever."
|
The spun yarn examples: |
Marx thus
provides an example involving spun yarn. & |
The capitalist would be earning "surplus value" and "exploiting" labor even if he were operating at a loss. |
A manufacturer of spun yarn
provides about £1,000 in capital - including £90 for labor - that produces a £90 increase in total capital - surplus value that is profit - or 9%.
However, after production, £500 of value still remains
in the fixed machinery. It adds no "value" to the yarn, and so can be
eliminated from the calculation.
|
Then, Marx takes his rationalizations even one step further. The
materials consumed and the minute values lost in the wear and tear of production
are referred to as "constant capital," since as commodities, their value is
fixed. Only the laborer adds new value, so this labor power is termed "variable
capital," although Marx must admit that as a practical matter it is as
"constant" as the other factors of production.
With this metamorphosis of economic
concepts into mathematical concepts by means of sly definitions, Marx proudly reduces his example by the
amount of the £410 worth of consumable capital. This leaves the £90 paid
for the labor that produced the surplus value of which £90 is an increase in the
capitalist's total capital - a profit in the yarn example - which Marx here refers to only in terms of the broader concept of surplus
value. |
|
After the mathematical cancellation step, surplus value - with its much higher "rates" - can substitute for profits when it comes to analysis of capital accumulation. |
This now meaningless figure has obvious importance for propaganda purposes. Marx thus gives it a special designation - "the rate of surplus value" - and uses it as a measure of "exploitation." After all, as Marx repeatedly notes, the rate of profits - unlike the rate of surplus value - is calculated against all the capital involved - resulting in much lower rates - just 9% in the yarn example - not nearly as useful for the propaganda purpose of emphasizing "exploitation."
Marx repeatedly insists that it is "the production of surplus value" that is the "compelling motive" of capitalist activity. This is clearly absurd.
But with the mathematical trick of canceling out from his calculations
both the consumed capital and the commodity values that replaced it, Marx is left
only with surplus value that is profits. This allows him to have his cake and
eat it too. |
Surplus labor:
& |
Labor time is "unnecessary," Marx
asserts, when expended beyond what is needed to produce subsistence values for
the worker. For a worker paid subsistence wages, pay is actually only for his "necessary" labor time. The rest is
"unpaid" labor time that the worker is compelled to give to the
exploiting capitalist who controls the necessary means of production. & |
Labor time is "unnecessary" when expended beyond what is needed to produce subsistence values for the worker. |
Compulsory
unpaid labor is just one step away from feudal bondage. (Who could be in favor of
feudalism?) It is just one step away from slavery, in that the worker has some
ability to shift about among different slave-master capitalists. (Who could be
in favor of slavery?)
However, as Marx later sets forth, all things are not equal. Without the capitalist's tools
and materials - and adequate management and supervision - our 19th century
unskilled laborer could work for a week without being
able to produce a small fraction of the yarn produced with them in a day. He
has been transformed into a "manufacturing labourer" dependent on
the capitalist workshop for his subsistence.
The laborer would have to acquire them rather than produce them since, as Marx notes, each day that the laborer produces yarn, his work consumes four days worth of consumable materials including wear and tear on equipment, "for, in the example we are considering, the production of the raw material and instruments of labour demand four working days - - -, and their conversion into yarn requires another such day." Thus, only by purchasing these materials and including their value in the value of his yarn can the laborer cover such costs - only thus can he turn "one working day into five."
|
Of course, if the capitalist's assets are expropriated and dedicated to the use of the workers, this problem is solved. "If this labourer were in possession of his own means of production, - - - he need not work beyond the time necessary for the reproduction of his means of subsistence," which Marx correctly notes would have to be expanded to include the time needed to maintain his productive assets - including a reserve against depreciation. He would then be obliged to exploit himself to maintain his working capital to the extent it depreciates during idleness - which he is obliged to do in order to sustain his output at the levels normal with the productive capabilities of the day.
Marx assures us that this rationalization is just “scientifi c analysis of value and surplus value.” However, the problem, as Schumpeter points out, is that Marx’ “scientific analysis of value and surplus value” simply does not conform to the plain facts of reality. See, Schumpeter "Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy," at segment on "Evaluation of Marx.
Marx assures us that this rationalization is just "scientific analysis of value and surplus value." (Absurd premises carried to their logical conclusion achieve absurd results.) In the spun yarn example, where half the labor time was for provision of surplus value, the rate of exploitation was 100%. For half his time, our laborer works like a slave.
Marx then spends some time demonstrating his accomplishment.
|
When using "the rate of surplus value," the Marxist implies that the capitalist interest brings nothing of value to the production process but the money with which the worker is paid, and is entitled to nothing else in return for it. |
Thus, Marx arrives at his definitions of "surplus value" and the "rate of surplus value."
|
With a 100% rate of surplus value, the wage laborer is being paid for only half his day, and is being forced to provide "unpaid" labor for the sole benefit of the capitalist for the other half. |
On the basis of such false premises - rationalizations completely detached from reality - Marx provides four senseless chapters on wages. Having eliminated the value of the other essential contributing factors to capitalist production, Marx can gaze amazedly at the absurdity he has himself created. A wage laborer, for example, who produces 6s. in value per day - a 12 hour day in the spun yarn example - will only be paid the 3s. per day that he and his family need to subsist.
This
"absurd" capitalist result is hidden by means of the wage system,
which makes it appear that the laborer is being paid for each and every hour
worked during the day - or for each piece produced. It is the role of the
"science" of Karl Marx to reveal the truth in the "hidden
substrata" underneath the surface appearance of the wage labor system. The
wage laborer is being paid for only half his day, and is being forced to provide
"unpaid" labor for the sole benefit of the capitalist for the other
half.
|
Please return to our Homepage and e-mail your name and comments.
Copyright © 2003 Dan Blatt